Abstract
Recently there has been some discussion concerning a particular type of enhancement, namely ‘moral enhancement’. However, there is no consensus on what precisely constitutes moral enhancement, and as a result the concept is used and defined in a wide variety of ways. In this article, we develop a clarificatory taxonomy of these definitions and we identify the criteria that are used to delineate the concept. We think that the current definitions can be distinguished from each other by the criteria used for determining whether an intervention is indeed moral enhancement. For example, some definitions are broad and include moral enhancement by any means, while other definitions focus only on moral enhancement by means of specific types of intervention (e.g. biomedical or genetic interventions). Moreover, for some definitions it suffices for an intervention to be aimed or intended to morally enhance a person, while other definitions only refer to ‘moral enhancement’ in relation to interventions that are actually effective. For all these differences in definitions we discuss some of their (more normative) implications. This shows that definitions are significantly less descriptive and more normative than they are regularly portrayed to be. We therefore hope that the taxonomy developed in this paper and the comments on the implications for the normative debate of the variety of definitions will provide conceptual clarity in a complex and highly interesting debate.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes
The debate on a possible distinction between ‘treatment’ and ‘enhancement’ is, of course, by no means exclusive to the moral enhancement debate. Many commentators have already discussed the relevance or irrelevance of such a distinction for the general debate on enhancement [20].
One might understand ‘moral capacities’ as being those capacities we actually use when making moral decisions (which capacities these are, is researched in moral psychology and neuroscience). For example, a recent review on the neurobiology of morality argues that it is most plausible to depict moral processes as requiring the engagement of both emotional and cognitive neural networks) [23]. However, ‘moral capacities’ might also be used to refer to those capacities one believes one should use when making moral decisions, or capacities that, when used more or better, would lead to better moral decisions. These capacities might, for example, constitute the capacity for sympathy and fairness [9] or cognitive capacities [1].
Of course, again, we should not mistake the debate on what to call these interventions with debate on the ethical validity of such interventions. Authors such as Harris can consistently claim: (1) that an intervention such as the one performed on Jack is not a moral enhancement, and (2) that there might be some cases where such an intervention is morally justified.
In this respect, Savulescu and Persson do mention at the end of their paper that ‘[s]uch interventions and such control are not plausibly moral enhancements of that person’ [30, p.417]. They mainly argue for the God Machine on the grounds that there would be many positive effects and as such their view perhaps does not differ that much from authors such as Harris.
References
Harris, John. 2011. Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics 25(2): 102–111.
Harris, John. 2012. What it’s like to be good. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21(3): 293–305.
Wasserman, David. 2013. When bad people do good things: Will moral enhancement make the world a better place. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101094.
Persson, Ingmar, and Julian Savulescu. 2008. The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to enhance the moral character of humanity. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25(3): 162–177.
Persson, Ingmar, and Julian Savulescu. 2011. The turn for ultimate harm: A reply to Fenton. Journal of Medical Ethics 37: 441–444.
Persson, Ingmar, and Julian Savulescu. 2012. Unfit for the future: The need for moral enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fenton, Elizabeth. 2010. The perils of failing to enhance: A response to Persson and Savulescu. Journal of Medical Ethics 36: 148–151.
Shook, J.R. 2012. Neuroethics and the possible types of moral enhancement. AJOB Neuroscience 3(4): 3–14.
DeGrazia, David. 2013. Moral enhancement, freedom, and what we (should) value in moral behaviour. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101157.
Hughes, James. 2011. After happiness, cyborg virtue. Free Inquiry 32(1): 1–7.
Harris, John. 2013. “Ethics is for bad guys!” putting the “moral” into moral enhancement. Bioethics 27(3): 169–173.
Harris, John. 2013. Moral progress and moral enhancement. Bioethics 27(5): 285–290.
Lev, Ori. 2012. Enhancing the capacity for moral agency. AJOB Neuroscience 3(4): 20–22.
Agar, Nicholas. 2013. A question about defining moral bioenhancement. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101153.
Walker, Mark. 2009. Enhancing genetic virtue. Politics and the Life Sciences 28(2): 27–47.
Douglas, Thomas. 2008. Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25(3): 228–245.
Douglas, Thomas. 2011. Moral enhancement via direct emotion modulation: A reply to John Harris. Bioethics 27(3): 160–168.
Parfit, Derek. 1989. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon.
Faust, Halley S. 2008. Should we select for genetic moral enhancement? A thought experiment using the MoralKinder (MK+) haplotype. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29: 397–416.
Daniels, Norman. 2000. Normal functioning and the treatment-enhancement distinction. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 9: 309–322.
Agar, Nicholas. 2010. Enhancing genetic virtue? Politics and the Life Sciences 29(1): 73–75.
Horstkötter, Dorothee, Ron Berghmans, and Guido de Wert. 2010. Moral enhancement for antisocial behavior? An uneasy relationship. AJOB Neuroscience 3(4): 26–28.
Pascual, Leo, Paulo Rodrigues, and David Gallardo-Pujol. 2013. How does morality work in the brain? A functional and structural perspective of moral behavior. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 7(65). doi:10.3389/fnint.2013.00065.
Santoni de Sio, Filippo, Hannah Maslen, and Nadira Faulmüller. 2012. The necessity of objective standards for moral enhancement. AJOB Neuroscience 3(4): 15–16.
Harris, John. 2013. Taking liberties with free fall. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101092.
Jotterand, Fabrice. 2011. “Virtue engineering” and moral agency: Will post- humans still need the virtues? AJOB Neuroscience 2(4): 3–9.
Simkulet, William. 2012. On moral enhancement. AJOB Neuroscience 3(4): 17–18.
Baertschi, Bernard. 2012. Neuromodulation in the service of moral enhancement. Brain Topography. doi:10.1007/s10548-012-0273-7.
Zarpentine, Chris. 2013. “The thorny and arduous path of moral progress”: Moral psychology and moral enhancement. Neuroethics 6: 141–153.
Savulescu, Julian, and Ingmar Persson. 2012. Moral enhancement, freedom, and the god machine. The Monist 95(3): 399–421.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Raus, K., Focquaert, F., Schermer, M. et al. On Defining Moral Enhancement: A Clarificatory Taxonomy. Neuroethics 7, 263–273 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-014-9205-4
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-014-9205-4
Keywords
- Moral enhancement
- Moral bioenhancement
- Definition
- Conceptual analysis