Neuroethics

, Volume 7, Issue 2, pp 159–172 | Cite as

The Science of Morality and its Normative Implications

Original Paper

Abstract

Neuromoral theorists are those who claim that a scientific understanding of moral judgment through the methods of psychology, neuroscience and related disciplines can have normative implications and can be used to improve the human ability to make moral judgments. We consider three neuromoral theories: one suggested by Gazzaniga, one put forward by Gigerenzer, and one developed by Greene. By contrasting these theories we reveal some of the fundamental issues that neuromoral theories in general have to address. One important issue concerns whether the normative claims that neuromoral theorists would like to make are to be understood in moral terms or in non-moral terms. We argue that, on either a moral or a non-moral interpretation of these claims, neuromoral theories face serious problems. Therefore, neither the moral nor the non-moral reading of the normative claims makes them philosophically viable.

Keywords

Morality Normativity Ethics Neuroscience Psychology 

References

  1. 1.
    Kant, I. 1996/1788. Critique of practical reason. In Practical philosophy, ed. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1788.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Boyd, R. 1988. How to be a moral realist. In Essays on moral realism, ed. G. Sayre-McCord, 181–228. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Copp, D. 2008. Darwinian skepticism about moral realism. Philosophical Issues 18(1): 186–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Joyce, R. 2002. The myth of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Joyce, R. 2006. The evolution of morality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Gazzaniga, M. 2005. The ethical brain. New York: Dana Press.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Mikhail, J. 2007. Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11(4): 143–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Hauser, M., L. Young, and F. Cushman. 2008. Reviving Rawls’s linguistic analogy: Operative principles and the causal structure of moral actions. In Moral psychology vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 107–143. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Dwyer, S. 2009. Moral dumbfounding and the linguistic analogy. Methodological implications for the study of moral judgment. Mind and Language 24(3): 274–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Sterelny, K. 2012. The evolved apprentice. How evolution made humans unique. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Gigerenzer, G. 2008. Moral intuition=fast and frugal heuristics? In Moral psychology vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 1–26. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Gigerenzer, G. 2010. Moral satisficing: Rethinking moral behavior as bounded rationality. Topics in Cognitive Science 2: 528–554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Simon, H. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics 69: 99–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Simon, H. 1956. Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review 63: 129–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Gigerenzer, G., P.M. Todd, and ABC Research Group. 1999. Simple heuristics that make us smart. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Gigerenzer, G. 2000. Adaptive thinking. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Gigerenzer, G., and R. Selten (eds.). 2001. Bounded rationality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Johnson, E., and D. Goldstein. 2003. Do defaults save lives? Science 302: 1338–1339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Lipsey, R.G., and K. Lancaster. 1956. The general theory of the second best. Review of Economic Studies 24: 11–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Todd, P.M., and G. Gigerenzer. 2007. Mechanisms of ecological rationality: Heuristics and environments that make us smart. In Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology, ed. R. Dunbar and L. Barrett. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Sunstein, C.R., and R.H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70(4): 1159–1202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Mill, J.S. 1998/1861. In Utilitarianism, ed. R. Crisp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Kagan, S. 1998. Normative ethics. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Lenman, J. 2000. Consequentialism and cluelessness. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29(4): 342–370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Gigerenzer, G. 2008. Reply to comments. In Moral psychology vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 41–46. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Gigerenzer, G., and T. Sturm. 2012. How (far) can epistemology be naturalized? Synthese 187(1): 243–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Sunstein, C.R. 2008. Fast, frugal and (sometimes) wrong. In Moral psychology, vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 27–31. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Greene, J.D., et al. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293: 2105–2108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 29.
    Greene, J.D., et al. 2004. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44: 389–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 30.
    Greene, J.D., et al. 2008. Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition 107: 1144–1154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Greene, J.D., et al. 2009. Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111: 364–371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Greene, J.D. 2008. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Moral psychology vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 35–79. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Greene, J. D. 2010. Notes onThe Normative Insignificance of Neuroscienceby Selim Berker. Available on http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~jgreene/GreeneWJH/Greene-Notes-on-Berker-Nov10.pdf (accessed May 2nd, 2012).
  34. 34.
    Greene, J. D. (unpublished). Beyond point-and-shoot morality: Why cognitive (neuro)science matters for ethics. Forthcoming on Ethics.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Haidt, J. 2001. The emotional dog and his rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108(4): 814–834.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Schwitzgebel, E., and F. Cushman. 2012. Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language 27(2): 135–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Berker, S. 2009. The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy and Public Affairs 37(4): 293–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    Haidt, J., and S. Kesebir. 2010. Morality. In Handbook of social psychology, 5th ed, ed. S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, and G. Lindzey, 797–832. Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Kahane, G. 2013. The armchair and the trolley: An argument for experimental ethics. Philosophical Studies 162(2): 421–445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Kahane, G., et al. 2012. The neural basis of intuitive and counterintuitive moral judgment. Social Cognitive Affective Neuroscience 7(4): 393–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. 41.
    Kahane, G., and N. Shackel. 2010. Methodological issues in the neuroscience of moral judgement. Mind and Language 25(5): 561–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Klein, C. 2011. The dual track theory of moral decision-making: A critique of the neuroimaging evidence. Neuroethics 4(2): 143–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. 43.
    McGuire, J., et al. 2009. A reanalysis of the personal/impersonal distinction in moral psychology research. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45(3): 577–580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. 44.
    Mikhail, J. 2008. Moral cognition and computational theory. In Moral psychology vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 81–91. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Moll, J., et al. 2005. The neural basis of human moral cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6: 799–809.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 46.
    Haidt, J. 2007. The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science 316(5827): 998–1002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. 47.
    Haidt, J. 2012. The righteous mind. Why we are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
  48. 48.
    Kamm, F. 2007. Intricate ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. 49.
    Singer, P. 2005. Ethics and intuitions. The Journal of Ethics 9: 331–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. 50.
    Sidgwick, H. 1907. The methods of ethics, 7th ed. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.European Institute of OncologyMilanItaly
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyKing’s College LondonLondonUK
  3. 3.The Uehiro Center for Practical EthicsUniversity of OxfordOxfordUK

Personalised recommendations