Skip to main content
Log in

Antigone and Addison’s Cato: Redeeming Exemplarity in Political Thought

  • Forum paper
  • Published:
International Journal of the Classical Tradition Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What does political theory gain from tragedy? Recent work by Bonnie Honig, Patchen Markell, Richard Halpern, and Tracy Strong (to name a few) pushes back against instrumentalist claims for art that reduce literary texts into moral lessons in how to be sympathetic to the experience of people unlike oneself. Honig and the rest appeal to Hannah Arendt’s suggestions in The Human Condition and elsewhere that the spectacularity, ephemerality, and unpredictability of dramatic performance—and the tragic tendency to showcase human finitude—transform the theater into “a space of freedom pursued for its own sake” (Richard Halpern, “Theater and democratic thought: Arendt to Rancière,” Critical Inquiry 27.3 (2011) 545–7, quotation from 571). Embedded in Honig’s arguments is the notion that tragedy is exemplary, and experienced as such, in that the characters in tragedy stand for a particular class or political values or problems. She sets the reading of critics who see in Antigone “a model of dissident politics” against her own interpretation of Antigone performing “Homeric/elite objections” to Athenian democracy: “the play airs through its two main characters…concerns about the costs of a particular democratic form of life.” In this paper I read Addison’s Cato as a hero who accomplishes an exemplary evasion of his own exemplary history by dodging his own legacy in history and literature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Patchen Markell also criticizes the stagnating effect of over-emphasis on character and under-emphasis on action that has burdened our understanding of the play in chapter three of his book Markell (2003) Bound By Recognition, Chicago (“Tragic recognition: action and identity in Antigone and Aristotle,” esp. 80–84).

  2. Bonnie Honig (2013), 18–20, 23ff.

  3. Robert Pippin (2005) The Persistence of Subjectivity: On the Kantian Aftermath. Cambridge, 2.

  4. Achille Mbembe (2001) On the Postcolony. Berkeley and Los Angeles, 128, 129.

  5. Sharon Krause (2012) “Non-sovereign freedom.” Presentation at Columbia University Political Theory Colloquium, 2012 (http://politicalscience.stanford.edu/sites/default/files/workshop-materials/pt_Krause.pdf).

  6. Recent thinking on “non-sovereign freedom” (a concept drawn from Arendt) appears in (to choose just two examples of a growing literature) Krause (n. 5) and Linda Zerilli (2005) Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom. Chicago, 168, 180, 187.

  7. Honig (n.2), 17, 19.

  8. Jean-Luc Nancy (1992) The Inoperative Community. Minneapolis, 3.

  9. Nancy is not quite a “mortalist humanist” but Honig’s characterization of its core idea “that we should dwell longer in grief or forge in grief new solidarities, or find in grievability a new social ontology of equality” is applicable to his arguments. She reminds us that “although we may all be mortals (with varying deaths and varying attitudes toward and experiences of death), we are, as Hannah Arendt insists along with Nietzsche, natals as well” (both quotations, 27). I share her reservations about mortalism and finitude and their magnetic force in current political thought, but am mostly interested here in The Inoperative Community’s comments on literature.

  10. Nancy touches on this point several times: see especially 58, 66, 140.

  11. Modifying Nancy’s comment (n. 8) 47.

  12. Nancy (n.8), 63.

  13. On the subjective and hermeneutic dynamics of “receiving” a classical text (“reception”), see William Batstone, “The point of reception theory,” especially 17-18 (“And so we find the uncanny within the heart of the familiar”) and Duncan Kennedy’s brief but provocative comments on “The uses of ‘reception’,” both in Martindale and Thomas eds. (2006) Classics and the Uses of Reception. Oxford and Malden, MA.

  14. Katherine Gaudet (2012) “Liberty and death: fictions of suicide in the new republic.” Early American Literature 47.3, 591–622, esp. 602.

  15. Lisa A. Freeman, “What’s love got to do with Addison’s ‘Cato’?” Studies in English Literature 1500-1900 39.3 (1999) 463-82, 463-64.

  16. Julie Ellison, “Cato’s tears.” ELH 63.3 (1996) 571–601; 579–80.

  17. Food for thought: a revision of the play appeared in 1764 called Cato. A Tragedy By Mr. Addison. Without the Love Scenes.

  18. Dana Villa writes: “To genuinely experience the unraveling power of thought is to risk not only inactivity, but cynicism and even nihilism. And yet, despite this risk, despite this danger, Arendt present the paralysis of thought as of urgent political and moral consequence because it slows people down” (his emphasis, 211). Villa (1999) Politics, Philosophy, Terror: Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt. Princeton.

  19. Gaudet (n.14), 591–92 (including the statistics on the number of novels featuring suicide).

  20. Ellison (n.16), 583.

  21. Nancy (n.8), 69 (both quotations in this paragraph).

  22. Nancy (n.8), 71.

  23. Pippin (n.3), 338 on Proust.

  24. Nancy (n.8), 79. Thanks to the panel organizers and participants.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joy Connolly.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Connolly, J. Antigone and Addison’s Cato: Redeeming Exemplarity in Political Thought. Int class trad 21, 317–325 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12138-014-0355-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12138-014-0355-x

Keywords

Navigation