Skip to main content
Log in

Causation in Physics and in Physicalism

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is widely thought that there is an important argument to be made that starts with premises taken from the science of physics and ends with the conclusion of physicalism. The standard view is that this argument takes the form of a causal argument for physicalism. Roughly, physics tells us that the physical realm is causally complete, and so minds (among other entities) must be physical if they are to interact with the world as we think they do. In what follows, I raise problems for this view. After an initial review of the causal argument, I begin my case by showing that the totality of physical truths do not deductively entail the causal completeness of the physical realm, using a double-prevention scenario and causation by omission to show that nonphysical causes of physical effects would not need to violate physical conservation laws. I then move on to raise problems for an inductive argument for causal completeness by drawing on the neo-Russellian view that there is no causation in fundamental physics, and so causation must itself be a realized or derived entity. I conclude by suggesting that the underlying problem is that the causal argument has fallen out of touch with the sophisticated understanding that philosophers have developed of the role of causation within physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the view that physics gives us good reason to reject physicalism, see for instance Wigner (1961), who takes the Von Neumann-Dirac collapse formulation of quantum mechanics to support mind–body dualism. Or see Barrett (2006), who contends that both collapse and no-collapse formulations support dualism.

  2. Taken from Papineau (2001: 9), but using Papineau’s (1993) formulation of the (P1) premise. Other proponents of causal arguments for physicalism include Lewis (1966), Davidson (1970), Peacocke (1979), Tye (1995, 2009), Levine (2001), and Melnyk (2003), Kim (2005).

  3. This is in contrast with the via negativa conception that defines “physical” as (roughly) the non-mental; see for example Montero (1999), Papineau (2001) and (2002), Levine (2001), and Tiehen (2016). One reason to prefer the theory-based conception in the present paper is that what we are interested in the way the science of physics in particular provides evidence for physicalism.

  4. There are physicalists who reject this token identity thesis, holding that mental events are realized or constituted by physical events rather than identical with them—for discussion, see Yablo (1992). Perhaps they can embrace a modified version of the causal argument that makes room for their position, but this is not something I will explore.

  5. See Stoljar (2015) and Tiehen (2018) for discussion.

  6. Cornman (1978) argues that Broad’s (1923) version of antiphysicalist interactionism is consistent with the conservation of energy but not with the law of the conservation of linear momentum. I mention this to highlight the need to bring in other conservation laws here.

  7. Leibniz (1998). Of course, many different critics objected to Descartes’s interactionism, but I single out Leibniz because his objection is based specifically on physical conservation laws.

  8. For further discussion relating Leibniz’s view to the case for Completeness, see Papineau (2001, 2002) and Montero (2006). Garber (1983) argues that Leibniz misrepresents Descartes’ position, while McLaughlin (1993) responds that Leibniz got Descartes right.

  9. The title of the pamphlet is standardly translated using “force,” but Helmholtz retrospectively understood his argument to concern energy. For the development of his thinking on the point, see Elkana (1974).

  10. Hergenhahn and Henley (2013: 223).

  11. Driesch (2013: 145).

  12. Dennett (1991: 35).

  13. Lewis (1990: 590). Beyond Dennett and Lewis, other philosophers who seem to take the conservation laws to rule out violations of Completeness include Fodor (1981), Lycan (1996), and Crane (2001). Here I am indebted to Montero (2006).

  14. Other authors who deny such an entailment include McLaughlin (1992) and Papineau (2001, 2002). They argue on different grounds than I do here; also, they endorse the inductive argument for Completeness that I reject in §3. See also Montero (2006) for skepticism that physics entails Completeness.

  15. Regarding double prevention, see for instance Hall (2000, 2004), Lewis (2000, 2004), Schaffer (2000, 2004), Gibb (2013, 2015a, 2015b), and Paul and Hall (2013).

  16. This is taken from Hall (2004: 271).

  17. Gibb (2013, 2015a, 2015b).

  18. Tiehen (2014).

  19. This is essentially the view of mental causation envisioned by Gibb (2013, 2015a, 2015b), with the caveat that she denies that absences can be causes—a position we will consider in Sect. 2.4—and so frames her view as giving the mental a kind of causal relevance to the physical without causing physical effects. In effect, Gibb frames her account as a way to reconcile a kind of dualist mental causation with Completeness, while I have framed my argument here as showing that Completeness can be false even if all actual physical truths hold.

  20. Objection: If (as we are assuming) the conservation of energy law holds at w*, then the 8-ball reaching the corner pocket does not counterfactually depend on the prevectoplasm intervening, since the law would have obtained even if the prevectoplasm had not intervened. Reply: By assumption, the conservation of energy principle holds as a law at w* at least partly because there is a nonphysical law ensuring that prevectoplasm prevents ectoplasm from interfering with physical processes. Once we counterfactually suppose this nonphysical law away (by supposing the prevectoplasm had not intervened in this case), we cannot assume the conservation of energy principle would continue to hold as a matter of law.

  21. This was the focus of Tiehen (2014).

  22. See Jackson (1998), Chalmers (1996, 2012), and Tiehen (2014). Or perhaps, as Jackson and Chalmers maintain, physicalism allows that the entailment base will include indexical truths in addition to physical truths and a that’s-all truth. I will ignore this complication here.

  23. On probability-raising theories, see for instance Suppes (1970) and Eells (1991); for interventionist approaches, Woodward (2003, 2009) and Hitchcock (2009); for counterfactual theories, Lewis (1973, 2000).

  24. Dowe (1992, 2000, 2001, 2004). Other defenders of broadly similar physical theories of causation include Aronson (1971), Fair (1979), Salmon (1984), Hall (2004), Kim (2007), and Ney (2009). I note that Fair develops his account in a way that allows for absence causation.

  25. Instead, he says double prevention is a form of “causation*” (Dowe: 2000), or “quasi-causation” (Dowe: 2001).

  26. Strictly speaking, my argument does not require the difference-making conception—it is for instance compatible with Fair’s (1979) non-standard physical theory that allows for absence causation. But because the most familiar way to defend absence causation is in connection with difference-making views, and because I find such views plausible anyway, I am willing to make them my focus here and treat them as a premise of my argument.

  27. Influential difference-making approaches to mental causation have been defended by Lepore & Loewer (1987), Yablo (1992), Loewer (2007), Woodward (2015), among others.

  28. See Schaffer (2000, 2004) for arguments that many of the causal claims advanced in the special sciences invoke absences. Loewer (2007) argues that difference-making mental causation is as much as physicalists can hope for, and that they should be content. Russo (2016) makes the empirical case that the physiological mechanisms underlying human action involve double prevention, in which case philosophers who deny that double prevention is causation will be forced to hold that mental events do not cause human actions.

  29. An anonymous referee notes that Kim (2007) acknowledges that it is the productive conception of causation rather than the difference-making one that is operative in his causal exclusion argument, which is broadly similar to the causal argument for physicalism. In that case, my argument would fail to saddle Kim with any burden he does not already willingly take on. However, there are other proponents of the causal argument for physicalism who operate with the difference-making conception, including as a paradigmatic example David Lewis—for his defense of the causal argument, see Lewis (1966), and for his counterfactual theory of causation, see Lewis (1973). In that case, my argument in this section exerts leverage on at least some proponents of the causal argument.

  30. Melnyk (2003: 289–290).

  31. For discussion see Russell (1913), Field (2003), Norton (2003), the essays contained Price and Corry (2007), Kutach (2013), Papineau (2013), Frisch (2014), Ney (2016), Loew (2017), and Haug (2019).

  32. Russell (1913: 1).

  33. See for instance Albert (2000) and several of the essays contained in Price and Corry (2007).

  34. Field (2003: 443).

  35. Papineau (2013) pursues this line of thought.

  36. Field (2003: 443), describing Cartwright (1979).

  37. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this point, giving as an example Anscombe’s (1971) view according to which we can perceive causal relations.

  38. Proponents of simplicity-based arguments for physicalism include Smart (1959), Brandt and Kim (1967), Churchland (1987), Hill (1991), Hill and McLaughlin (1999), McLaughlin (2007), and Block and Stalnaker (1999).

  39. Two authors who have explored conclusions similar to mine—but not arguments similar to mine—are Ney (2016) and Haug (2019). Ney argues that there is a tension between the causal argument for physicalism and causal anti-fundamentalism. She then suggests that this gives us reason to reject anti-fundamentalism. In effect, Ney and I agree on what the decision points are in this debate, we just disagree on which decisions should be made at those points. Haug acknowledges there is a tension between the causal argument and causal anti-fundamentalism, and proposes to meet that challenge by developing two distinct but complementary arguments for physicalism: one argument that is causal and draws on evidence from various sciences, and one that is non-causal and focuses on fundamental physics. The overall view is at odds with mine, but there is at least this much agreement: I too say that the causal argument alone cannot get us all the way to physicalism, and at best can work by being supplemented with a non-causal argument.

  40. Papineau (2001, 2002).

References

  • Albert, D. (2000). Time and chance. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1971). Causality and determination: An inaugural lecture. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aronson, J. (1979). On the grammar of ‘cause.’ Synthese, 22, 414–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. A. (2006). A quantum-mechanical argument for mind-body dualism. Erkenntnis, 65, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108, 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R., & Kim, J. (1967). The logic of the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 64(17), 515–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1923). Mind and its place in nature. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1979). Causal laws and effective strategies. Nous, 13(4), 419–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1987). Epistemology in the age of neuroscience. Journal of Philosophy, 84(10), 544–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornman, J. W. (1978). A nonreductive identity thesis about mind and body, in J. Feinberg (ed.) Reason and responsibility: Readings in some basic problems of philosophy. Encino, CA: Dickinson Publishing Company

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The cconscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the world. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events,” in L. Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Experience and theory. Amherst: Massachusetts University Press

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Back Bay Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. (1929). Quantum mechanics of many-electrons systems. Proceedings of the Royal Society, 123, 714–733.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (1992). Wesley Salmon’s process theory of causality and the conserved quantity theory. Philosophy of Science, 59(2), 195–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2001). A counterfactual theory of prevention and ‘causation’ by omission. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(2), 216–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2004). Causes are physically connected to their effects: Why preventers and omissions are not causes, in C. R. Hitchcock (ed.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science: 189–196

  • Driesch, H. (2013). The history and theory of vitalism. Hesperides Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eells, E. (1991). Probabilistic causality. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elkana, Y. (1974). The discovery of the conservation of energy. Hutchinson Educational.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fair, D. (1979). Causation and the flow of energy. Erkenntnis, 14, 219–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2003). Causation in a physical world. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 435–460). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind-body problem. Scientific American, 244, 114–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2014). Causal reasoning in physics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. (1983). Mind, body, and the laws of nature in Descartes and Leibniz. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 8, 105–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. C. (2013) Mental causation and double prevention, in S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, and R. D. Ingthorsson (eds.) Mental causation and ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gibb, S. C. (2015a). Defending dualism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115, 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. C. (2015b). The causal closure principle. Philosophical Quarterly, 65(261), 626–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2000). Causation and the price of transitivity. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 198–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haug, M. (2019). No microphysical causation? no problem: Selective causal skepticism and the structure of completeness-based arguments for physicalism. Synthese, 196(3), 1187–1208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hergenhahn, B. R. and T. Henley (2013) An introduction to the history of psychology, 7th Edition. Wadsworth Publishing

  • Hill, C. (1991) Sensations: A defense of type materialism. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hill, C., & McLaughlin, B. (1999). There are fewer things in reality than are dreamt of in Chalmers’ philosophy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59, 445–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2009). Causal modeling. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2007) Causation and mental causation, in in B. McLaughlin and J. Cohen (eds.) Debates in philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. 227–242

  • Kutach, D. (2013). Causation and its basis in fundamental physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1998). Theodicy: Essays on the goodness of God, the freedom of man and the origin of evil. Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Loewer, B. (1987). Mind matters. Journal of Philosophy, 84(11), 630–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63, 17–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1990) What experience teaches, page references to reprint in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Guzeldere (eds.) Consciousness: Philosophical debates. Bradford Books

  • Lewis, D. K. (2000). Causation as influence. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 182–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (2004). Void and object. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 277–290). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loew, C. (2017). Causation, Physics, and Fit. Synthese, 194(6), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2007). Mental causation, or something near enough. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 243–264). Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Philosophy of mind. In N. Bunnin & E. P. Tsui-James (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. P. (1992). The rise and fall of British emergentism. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction?: Prospects for nonreductive physicalism. De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. P. (2007). On the limits of a priori physicalism. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (1993). Descartes on mind-body interaction and the conservation of motion. Philosophical Review, 102, 155–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (2003). A physicalist manifesto: Thoroughly modern materialism. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (1999). The body problem. Nous, 33, 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2006). What does the conservation of energy have to do with physicalism? Dialectica, 60(4), 383–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2009). Physical causation and difference-making. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 737–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2016). Microphysical causation and the case for physicalism. Analytic Philosophy, 57(1), 141–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2003). Causation as folk science. Philosophers’ Imprint, 3(4), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. 1993. Philosophical naturalism. Blackwell Publishing

  • Papineau, D. (2001). The rise of physicalism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2013). Causation is macroscopic but not irreducible. In S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, & R. D. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Mental causation and ontology (pp. 126–152). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. and N. Hall. Causation: A user’s guide. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Peacocke, C. (1979). Holistic explanation: Action, space, interpretation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H., & Corry, R. (2007). Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1913). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, A. (2016). Kim’s dilemma: Why mental causation is not productive”. Synthese, 193(7), 2185–2203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2000). Causation by disconnection. Philosophy of Science, 67(2), 285–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2004. Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation, in C. R. Hitchcock (ed.) Contemporary debates in philosophy of Science: 197–216

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. 2015. Physicalism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physicalism/>. Accessed 10 Dec 2021.

  • Suppes, P. A probabilistic theory of causality. Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Company

  • Tiehen, J. (2014). A priori scrutability and that’s all. Journal of Philosophy, 111(12), 649–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiehen, J. (2016). Physicalism requires functionalism: A new formulation and defense of the via negativa. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(1), 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiehen, J. (2018). Physicalism. Analysis, 78(3), 537–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited: Materialism without phenomenal concepts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P (1961) Remarks on the mind-body question. Reprinted in J. A. Wheeler and W. H. Zurek (eds.), Quantum theory and measurement. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 1983

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2015). Interventionism and causal exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(2), 303–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2009). Agency and interventionist theories. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101(2), 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin Tiehen.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tiehen, J. Causation in Physics and in Physicalism. Acta Anal 37, 471–488 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00503-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00503-y

Keywords

Navigation