Extending the Transparency Method beyond Belief: a Solution to the Generality Problem

Abstract

According to the Transparency Method (TM), one can know whether one believes that P by attending to a question about the world—namely, ‘Is P true?’ On this view, one can know, for instance, whether one believes that Socrates was a Greek philosopher by attending to the question ‘Was Socrates a Greek philosopher?’ While many think that TM can account for the self-knowledge we can have of such a belief—and belief in general—fewer think that TM can be generalised to account for the self-knowledge we can have of other propositional attitudes, such as our desires, intentions, wishes and so on. Call this the Generality Problem. In the present paper, I contrast my own attempt to solve the Generality Problem with several recent ones. I argue that in order to extend TM beyond belief, we must look to the concepts underpinning each kind of mental state. Doing so, I argue, reveals a series of outward-directed questions that can be attended to, in order to know what one desires, intends, wishes and so on. Call this the conceptual approach to extending TM. I support the conceptual approach in the present paper by showing how it generates Moore-Paradoxical sentences that are analogous to the case of belief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Notes

  1. 1.

    Proponents of the inner sense view include Lycan (1996), Armstrong (1968), Nichols and Stich (2003) and Goldman (2006). According to this view, we acquire self-knowledge of our mental states by looking inside, or by employing our own ‘internal monitor’, as Lycan (1996, p. 33) puts it. For a discussion of some of the most recent objections to the inner sense view, see Byrne (2018, Ch. 2). While Byrne does not think that any of these objections present a ‘knock-down refutation’ (2018, p. 49) of the view, he does think that there are ‘grounds for dissatisfaction [and that it] is time to examine some leading alternatives’ (2018, p. 49).

  2. 2.

    Another rival view to the inner sense view is called neo-expressivism. It is defended by Bar-On (2004) and Finkelstein (2003). According to this view, we do not detect our mental states, but rather express them. I will not consider this view in this paper.

  3. 3.

    Gordon, alternatively, calls this the ‘belief only’ (2007, p.155) objection.

  4. 4.

    Like Byrne (2018), I also think that TM can be extended to sensations. In this paper, however, I am only concerned with showing how TM can be applied to propositional attitudes.

  5. 5.

    In contrasting ‘inward-directed’ questions with ‘outward-directed’ questions, I am following Cassam (2014, p. 3), Moran (2004, p. 457) and Finkelstein (2003, p. 161).

  6. 6.

    Moran also attributes this negative thesis to TM when he says that the view does not involve ‘an “inward” glance or… observation of one’s own behaviour’ (2001, p. 101). Not all philosophers attribute this negative thesis to TM, however. Silins (2012), for example, says, ‘it remains perfectly possible that we obtain self-knowledge through inner observation and the transparency method at the same time’ (2012, p. 305). In my view, Silins’ ‘compatibilism’, which entails a rejection of the negative thesis, is in tension with TM’s positive claim. This is a point I do not have the space to argue for in this paper, however.

  7. 7.

    For an account of how TM is applicable to belief, see Moran (2001), Fernández (2013) and Byrne (2005, 2018).

  8. 8.

    Another reason to accept TM, some have argued, is that is captures the phenomenology of self-attributing a belief. See Valaris (2014) for a defence of this claim.

  9. 9.

    Moore’s Paradox is named after the English philosopher G.E. Moore. As Green and Williams (2007, p. 5) point out, Moore is careful to distinguish between paradox and absurdity. Moore claims it would be absurd for a speaker to utter a MP sentence; and it is paradoxical that such an absurd sentence is not contradictory. The following MP sentence is an example that Moore himself provides: ‘I went to the pictures last Tuesday, but I don’t believe I did’ (1942, p. 543).

  10. 10.

    Following Cassam (2010), I understand judgements to be conscious mental actions, which are related to beliefs, which are typically more stable, longstanding, mental states. Cassam would disagree, however, that judgement and belief go together with the kind of congruity I am proposing here. Such a discussion is beyond the scope of this paper, however, which is after all not a thorough assessment of whether TM is a successful method for self-knowledge of belief, but instead an attempt to apply it to other propositional attitudes.

  11. 11.

    It would also be absurd for someone to judge that P is the case and claim that they have no beliefs either way about P. Consider someone who were to avow the following: ‘I judge that Nouméa is the capital city of New Caledonia, but I neither believe it or disbelieve it’.

  12. 12.

    See Schwitzgebel (2010) for a discussion about how to classify cases where there is an apparent mismatch between what a person believes and what they occurrently judge to be the case.

  13. 13.

    For a recent critique of Byrne’s approach, see Boyle (2019, pp. 1019–1024).

  14. 14.

    It is interesting to compare Carruthers’ criticism of TM: that it is only applicable to sensory-based beliefs, with Dorit Bar-On’s criticism of TM: that there is no way to extend TM to sensory-based beliefs (see 2004, p. 118). These distinct criticisms illustrate how differently TM has been represented in the literature.

  15. 15.

    I will only be concerned with how we know our occurrent conscious desires. As Krista Lawlor points out, we sometimes become aware of our unconscious desires by ‘inference’ (2009, p. 49), e.g. by testimony or therapy. This method of achieving self-knowledge of our desires would not conform to TM. This shows that TM is not the only way one can know what one desires.

  16. 16.

    In what follows, I consider the terms ‘desire’ and ‘want’ to be analogous.

  17. 17.

    It has been pointed out to me that some people use the term ‘believable’ differently to the way that I do here. Some use the term to refer to the upper threshold of epistemic possibility. For example, one might say ‘It’s not believable that the LA Kings will win the Stanley Cup’ to mean that it is very unlikely the LA Kings will win. Given this interpretation, the sentence ‘It’s not believable that the LA Kings will win the Stanley Cup, but I believe they will’ does not sound very Moore-Paradoxical. This is because there is a significant gap between finding something believable, in this epistemic threshold sense, and actually believing it. This would, therefore, not make it a good guide for determining what one believed. If we were to interpret DES in this same way, such that ‘desirable’ referred to an objective threshold of what is typically desired by people, then DES would be rendered even more implausible than I have suggested. This is because the connection between what one desires and what one deems desirable (in this objective threshold sense) is not a very congruous one. For example, a smoker may deem it ‘undesirable’ in this sense to have a cigarette, yet still have a desire for one.

  18. 18.

    I use these two forms to distinguish between desires which bring about actions (‘ϕ’); versus those that are about states of affairs (‘P’).

  19. 19.

    It may be objected that we often imagine things will bring us pleasure or satisfaction, and yet do not want to do them. For example, there may be three movies showing simultaneous at a cinema complex: Jaws, Alien and Scarface—all movies I think I would enjoy. Suppose I can only see one and come to pick Jaws. I would not say after making this choice that I lack a desire to see Alien or Scarface. I would say that I still believe that both would bring me pleasure or satisfaction, and so I think I have a desire to see both. However, since I believe that Jaws would be more pleasurable (or enjoyable) than the two other movies I decide to see it—and may even say that I do not want to see Alien or Scarface. It is important to note that the sense of ‘want’ in this context should be understood as shorthand for preference and should not be construed as denoting a lack of a desire to see Alien or Scarface.

  20. 20.

    See also Bilgrami (2006), who discusses the connection between intention and commitment.

  21. 21.

    As in the case of belief and desire, the conceptual approach should not be understood as an infallible guide to intention.

  22. 22.

    The English subjunctive can, of course, be used in various other forms. Consider Adam’s (Adams 1970, p. 92) famous example, ‘if Oswald hadn’t shot Kennedy, someone else would have’. This sentence suggests that the speaker believes that Oswald did kill Kennedy and that Kennedy would have been shot by someone else, if Oswald did not do it.

  23. 23.

    I thank an anonymous peer reviewer for suggesting this problem to me.

References

  1. Adams, E. (1970). Subjunctive and indicative conditionals. Foundations of Language, 6, 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anscombe, G. E. M. ([1957] 2000) Intention. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  3. Armstrong, D. M. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ashwell, L. (2013). Deep, dark… or transparent? Knowing our desires. Philosophical Studies, 165, 245–256.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking my mind: expression and self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Barz, W. (2015). Transparent introspection of wishes. Philosophical Studies, 172, 1993–2023.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bilgrami, A. (2006). Self-knowledge and resentment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Boyle, M. (2011). Transparent self-knowledge. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 85, 223–241.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Boyle, M. (2019). Transparency and reflection. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 1012–1039. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2019.1565621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Bratman, M. ([1987] 1999) Intention, plans, and practical reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

  11. Byrne, A. (2005). Introspection. Philosophical Topics, 33, 79–104.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Byrne, A. (2011). Transparency, belief, intention. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, 85, 201–221.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Byrne, A. (2012). Knowing what I want. In J. Lui & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the self: new essays (pp. 165–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Byrne, A. (2018). Transparency and self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: an integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cassam, Q. (2010). Judging, believing and thinking. Philosophical Issues, 20, 80–95.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cassam, Q. (2014). Self-knowledge for humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Fernández, J. (2007). Desire and self-knowledge. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 517–536.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Fernández, J. (2013). Transparent minds: a study of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Finkelstein, D. (2003). Expression and the inner. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Gertler, B. (2011). Self-knowledge and the transparency of belief. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Self-knowledge (pp. 125–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Gordon, R. M. (2007). Ascent routines for propositional attitudes. Synthese, 159, 151–165.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Green, M., & Williams, J. (2007). Introduction. In M. Green & J. Williams (Eds.), Moore’s paradox: new essays on belief, rationality, and the first person (pp. 3–36). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ‘If only’ (2020) Cambridge Dictionary [online]. Retrieved from: https://dictionary.cambridge.org/grammar/british-grammar/if-only. Accessed 20 June 2020.

  27. Lawlor, K. (2009). Knowing what one wants. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 47–75.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G.E. Moore (pp. 535–677). Evanston: Tudor.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Moran, R. (2004). Replies to heal, Reginster, Wilson, and Lear. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 455–472.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Moran, R. (2012). Self-knowledge, “transparency”, and the forms of activity. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 211–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: an integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Paul, S. K. (2012). How we know what we intend. Philosophical Studies, 161, 327–346.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Saemi, A. (2015). Aiming at the good. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45, 197–219.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgement and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531–553.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Schroeder, T. (2004). Three faces of desire. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Shoemaker, S. (1996). The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Silins, N. (2012). Judgement as a guide to belief. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 295–327). Oxford: Oxford. University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Sinhababu, N. (2017a). Human nature: how desire explains action, thought, and feeling. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Sinhababu, N. (2017b). Desire and aesthetic pleasure. Australasian Philosophical Review, 1, 95–99.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Valaris, M. (2014). Self-knowledge and the phenomenological transparency of belief. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper were presented to audiences at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference in Adelaide in 2017 and to the Philosophy Society at the University of Western Australia in 2018. I thank everyone who took part in those enlightening discussions. I would like to thank Miri Albahari, Nin Kirkham, Daniel Stoljar, Alex Byrne, André Gallois, Sean Ramsey and Harriet Levenston for feedback and advice on earlier versions of the paper. I also would like to thank an anonymous referee of this journal for the insightful comments.

Author information

Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam J. Andreotta.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andreotta, A.J. Extending the Transparency Method beyond Belief: a Solution to the Generality Problem. Acta Anal (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-020-00447-9

Download citation

Keywords

  • Self-knowledge
  • Transparency
  • Introspection
  • Belief
  • Desire
  • Intention