Skip to main content
Log in

Visual Experience: Cognitive Penetrability and Indeterminacy

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discusses a counterexample to the thesis that visual experience is cognitively impenetrable. My central claim is that sometimes visual experience is influenced by the perceiver’s beliefs, rendering her experience’s representational content indeterminate. After discussing other examples of cognitive penetrability, I focus on a certain kind of visual experience— that is, an experience that occurs under radically nonstandard conditions—and show that it may have indeterminate content, particularly with respect to low-level properties such as colors and shapes. I then explain how this indeterminacy depends on the perceiver’s beliefs or thoughts. Finally, I attempt to generalize the case and show how other sorts of visual experiences can also be penetrated by beliefs and, hence, be indeterminate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an overview of this position, see Robbins (2009); cf. Macpherson (2011), § 2.

  2. This is Siegel’s stronger characterization, which differs from the weaker one in that it precludes cognitive influence due to selection or attention. Cf. Siegel (2011) p. 4.

  3. Cf. Macpherson (2011), pp. 12-14.

  4. Walton argues that we indirectly see objects through photographs, but he (1990, ch. 8) also offers a general account of depiction in which by looking at a picture, we are imagining seeing the depictum. Being “penetrated” by the imagination, the visual state we end up having in looking at a picture represents the depicted object (this “imaginative penetrability” is akin to what Macpherson requires for her two-stage mechanism). From the intentionalistic perspective, imagining seeing may simply be considered as a kind of non-veridical visual experience of the depictum.

  5. On some of these views, we may simultaneously visually experience the depictum and the picture’s surface; and on other views, in experiencing the depictum, we cannot experience the surface. This difference is not important here.

  6. Hopkins (1998), Peacocke (1987), cf. Budd (1993) and Hyman’s (2006) three principles.

  7. In fact, the argument can be adjusted to accord even with Goodman’s (1976) and Kulvicki’s (2006) accounts, in which a picture, much like a verbal description, simply refers to the depictum. When a picture, much like a description, is perceived as referring to sparser scenarios, something in the way we perceive it changes (cf. Siegel’s [2006] Cyrillic text example). And since this is, as I will show, due to the influence of belief, pictorial indeterminacy is an example of cognitive penetrability on these accounts as well.

  8. This is a summary of my argument in Chasid (2007), §2.

  9. See Boghossian and Velleman (1989), Dretske (2003), Pace (2007), Schroer (2002), Smith (2008) and Tye (2002).

  10. For criticism of Dretske’s view (2003), see references in note 9.

  11. Note that the suggested mechanism does not include a trivial kind of belief influence; it is not that we fail to attend to the picture’s grey hue while experiencing the depictum, and hence we experience it indeterminately. Normally, we cannot avoid having the grey phenomenal aspect as part of the visual experience of the depictum, but because we believe that the depictum is not being depicted as grey, our experience of it is rendered indeterminate. For a thorough discussion on why such cases do not involve the change of attention, see Macpherson (2011), 20-23.

References

  • Boghossian, P., & Velleman, J. D. (1989). Color as a secondary quality. Mind, 98, 81–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Budd, M. (1993). How pictures look. In D. Knowles & J. Skorupski (Eds.), Virtue and taste (pp. 154–175). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chasid, A. (2007). Content-free pictorial realism. Philosophical Studies, 135, 375–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2011). The problem of perception. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/perception-problem/.

  • Dretske, F. (2003). Experience as representation. Philosophical Issues, 13, 67–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2010). Philosophy of perception. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. H. (1961). Art and illusion. London: Phaidon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of art. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image, and experience. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, J. (2006). The objective eye: Color, form and reality in the theory of art. Chicago: U of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2006). On images. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2011). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (early view), 1–38.

  • Newall, M. (2009). Pictorial experience and seeing. British Journal of Aesthetics, 49, 129–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newall, M. (2011). What is a picture? New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Pace, M. (2007). Blurred vision and the transparency of experience. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88(3), 328–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1987). Depiction. Philosophical Review, 96, 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, P. (2009). Modularity of mind. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (2009 Edition), URL= <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modularity-mind/>.

  • Schroer, R. (2002). Seeing it all clearly: the real story on blurry vision. American Philosophical Quarterly, 39(3), 297–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2011). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Nous (early view), 1-22.

  • Smith, A. D. (2008). Translucent experiences. Philosophical Studies, 140(2), 197–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Noûs, 36(1), 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1984). Transparent pictures: on the nature of photographic realism. Critical Inquiry, 11, 246–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Cambridge: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1987). Painting as an art. Princeton: Princeton UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1998). On pictorial representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56, 217–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zemach, E. (1999). Look, this is Zeus! In M. Krausz & R. Shusterman (Eds.), Interpretation, relativism and the metaphysics of culture (pp. 311–333). New York: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alon Chasid.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Chasid, A. Visual Experience: Cognitive Penetrability and Indeterminacy. Acta Anal 29, 119–130 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-013-0201-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-013-0201-9

Keywords

Navigation