Skip to main content
Log in

The Clay of Evolution: Megalomania in (Evolutionary) Psychology

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article is an attempt to reply to a number of theoretical and epistemological issues frequently addressed in contemporary evolutionary psychology. We adopt a critical approach to both the empiricist conceit so often underlying the discipline and its core premises around the relationship between mind and biological evolution. As an alternative we take a constructivist view from which we propose to broach that relationship through the so-called Baldwin effect. That phenomenon, widely known among evolutionary biologists today, enables us to elude simplistic approaches to the problem of the relationship between psychology and evolution. It also affords a perspective for re-focusing the issues on the activity of organisms and the classic inter-connections among phylogenesis, historiogenesis and ontogenesis. The study concludes with a warning about the limitations to explanation that should be assumed by any psychological postulate with universally comprehensive pretensions, an issue evocative of the inevitable and structural crisis in which psychology should agree to transpire.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Tradition’ insofar as texts on the discipline’s crisis can be found in the late nineteenth to early twentieth century institutional ‘foundation’ of scientific psychology, a circumstance that has led to a proposal for a specific bibliographic genre (Blanco 2002). The authors who first addressed the crisis would include, for instance, Willy in 1897, Gutberlet in 1898, Stern in 1900, Kostilff in 1911 and Bühler and Vigotsky, both in 1927. Although not overly prevalent in the literature, texts and monographs on the crisis have periodically dotted the editorial landscape and even revisited more classic studies (Caparrós 1991; VV.AA. 2006; Sturm and Mülberger 2012; Wieser 2016). The question that may be posed, then, is whether such a belaboured crisis is more an opportunity than a stumbling block for psychology; or as Blanco (2002) perceptively asked, whether the history of the crisis of psychology is rather a history of the successive crises affecting western subjectivity from the Modern Age to date. That hypothesis will echo throughout the considerations with which we conclude this article.

  2. Deeming biological to be more material than psychological reality is bias because the body is only more real than the mind in the (trivial) sense that its existence is bound to what we perceive as a touchable shape, something that takes up space. Unless we believe in immaterial reality, however, any manner of existence is tied to practice and objects, material things (Bueno 1990; Coole and Frost 2010; Fox and Alldred 2019). Some dimensions of the body are not phenomenic but conceptual (or phenomenic only through devices such as microscopes or mathematical formulae): our neurons, not to mention bodily motion or biomechanics, are cases in point.

  3. Whilst the authors mention, albeit only in passing, that ‘the brain and the body are directly affected by the mind itself, which operates as a “social organ” that converts relational experiences in the brain and somatic processes’ (p. 2), they draw no theoretical implication from that assertion. The idea that the mind is a social organ, as we shall suggest later, can be readily reintegrated into a theoretical evolutionary-psychological structure that reverts to the starting point: biological reality on the one hand and psychological reality, fruit of the former, on the other.

  4. Zagaria, Andò and Zennaro’s epistemic choices are not aseptic when identifying valid representatives: rather they entail visibilising certain psychological tendencies (such as psychoanalysis, cognitivism and neuroscience) and invisibilising others (cultural, genetic, ecological psychology, to name a few). The same can be said of the epistemological structure proposed, where they opt ‘naturally’ for certain conceits (using the Kuhnian idea of paradigm, for instance) over others. As we have been contending all along, no choice is devoid of values and commitments, no matter how objective it may claim to be.

  5. The authors of the article mention epigenetic premises (marginally) (‘[e]pigenetic variations are comprehended as well, because it is demonstrated that they are hereditable and can be selected in the evolution process’, p. 15), while asserting that the gene is widely accepted as the unit of selection, a contention scantly compatible with epigenetic interpretations.

References

  • Baldwin, J. M. (1896). A new factor in evolution. The American Naturalist, 30, 441–451 536-553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, J. M. (1917). Development and evolution (2nd ed.). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltes, P. B., Reuter-Lorenz, P. A., & Rösler, F. (Eds.). (2006). Lifespan development and the brain. The perspective of biocultural co-constructivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanco, F. (2002). El cultivo de la mente. Un ensayo histórico-critico sobre la cultura psicológica. Madrid: Antonio Machado.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boakes, R. A. (1984). From Darwin to Behaviourism. Psychology and the mind of Animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1983). The eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian evolutionary theories in the decades around 1900. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. I. (1977). Perception. Theory and Commitment. The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, G. (1990). Materia. Oviedo: Pentalfa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, R. B. (1991). Multiple metaphors for a singular idea. Developmental Psychology, 27(1), 23–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caparrós, A. (1991). Crisis de la psicología: ¿singular o plural? Aproximación a algo más que un concepto historiografico. Anuario de Psicologia, 51, 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castro, J., & Loredo, J. C. (2015). Evolution, activity and assembled mediation: A neo-Baldwinian response to the universalism of evolutionary psychology. Culture & Psychology, 21(1), 111–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castro, J., & Loredo, J. C. (2018). Psytizenship: Sociocultural mediations in the historical shaping of western citizen. In A. Rosa & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 479–500). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coole, D., & Frost, S. (Eds.). (2010). New materialisms: Ontology, agency and politics. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. W. (1997). The symbolic specie. The co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, T. M., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2011). The dynamics of ontogeny: A Neuroconstructivist perspective on genes, brains, cognition and behavior. Progress in Brain Research, 189, 23–33.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1987). Neural Darwinism: The theory of neuronal group selection. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, N. J., & Alldred, P. (2019). New materialism. In P. A. Atkinson, S. Delamont, A. Cernat, J. W. Sakshaug, & M. Williams (Eds.), SAGE research methods foundations. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, B. (2014). Social construction, evolution and cultural universals. Culture & Psychology, 20(3), 416–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinton, G. E., & Nowlan, S. J. (1987). How learning can guide evolution. Complex Systems, 1, 495–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. S. (1942). Evolution. The modern synthesis. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (2013). Prospect. In T. Ingold & G. Palsson (Eds.), Biosocial Becomings: Integrating social and biological anthropology (pp. 1–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (1995). Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: The Lamarckian dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2000). Organisms can be proud to be their own designers. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 7(1), 45–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loredo, J. C. (2019). Psychology as a technique of Subjectivation. Papeles del Psicólogo, 40(1), 31–38 http://www.papelesdelpsicologo.es/ico/pdf_ico.png.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loy, I., Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1992). El funcionalismo en perspectiva. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 13(2–3), 197–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. (1987). When learning guides evolution. Nature, 329(29), 761–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. (1998). Shaping life. Genes, embryos and evolution. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, C. (2003). Evolution, development, and the individual Acquisition of Traits: What We’ve learned since Baldwin. In B. H. Weber & D. J. Depew (Eds.), Evolution and learning. The Baldwin effect reconsidered (pp. 115–139). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, J. (2008). Los retos actuales del darwinismo. ¿Una teoría en crisis? [The current challenges of Darwinism. A theory in crisis? ]. Madrid: Síntesis.

  • Oyama, S. (2000). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution (2ª ed.). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez, M. (2011). El Mito del cerebro creador. Cuerpo, cultura y conducta. Madrid: Alianza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pérez, M. (2018). Thinking psychology beyond the mind and the brain: A trans-theoretical approach. Papeles del Psicólogo, 39(3), 161–173 http://www.papelesdelpsicologo.es/English/2875.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quartz, S. R., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development. A constructivist manifesto. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 537–556.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ramírez, E. (2013). Life-in-the-making: Epigenesis, biocultural environments and human Becomings. In T. Ingold & G. Palsson (Eds.), Biosocial Becomings: Integrating social and biological anthropology (pp. 59–83). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (1987). Darwin and the evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sampedro, J. (2013). Deconstruyendo a Darwin. Los enigmas de la evolución a través de la nueva genética. Barcelona: Planeta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990a). James, la selección natural y el funcionalismo. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990b). Funcionalismo y teoría de la selección orgánica. Revisión de algunos problemas conceptuales en el origen de la psicología comparada. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 53–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990c). Reconsideración histórica de la selección natural. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 517–528.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez, J. C., & Loredo, J. C. (2007). In circles we go. Baldwin’s theory of organic selection and its current uses: A constructivist view. Theory & Psychology, 17(1), 33–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez, J. C., & Loredo, J. C. (2009). Constructivisms from a genetic point of view. A critical classification of current tendencies. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 43(4), 332–349.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, J. (2004). Embryology, Epigenesis and evolution. Taking Development Seriously. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturm, T., & Mülberger, A. (2012). Crisis discussions in psychology. New historical and philosophical perspectivas. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(2), 425–433.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Turney, P., & Whytley, D. (1996). Evolution, learning and instinct: 100 years of the Baldwin effect. Evolutionay Computation, 4(3), v-viii.

    Google Scholar 

  • VV.AA. (2006). La crisis de la psicología. Anuario de Psicología, 37(1–2).

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1997). The historical meaning of the crisis of psychology. In R. Rieber, & J. Wolloc (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (pp. 233–344). New York, London: Plenum Press.

  • Weber, B. H., & Depew, D. J. (Eds.). (2003a). Evolution and learning. The Baldwin effect reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, B., & Depew, D. (Eds.). (2003b). Learning, meaning and emergence: Possible Baldwinian mechanisms for evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wieser, M. (2016). Psychology’s “crisis” and the need for reflection. A Plea for modesty in psychological theorizing. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Sciences, 50(3), 359–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagaria, A., Andò, A., & Zennaro, A. (2020). Psychology: a Giant with Feet of Clay. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 54(3), 521–562.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This study was not funded.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jorge Castro-Tejerina.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

José Carlos Loredo-Narciandi declares that he has no conflict of interest. Jorge Castro-Tejerina declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Loredo-Narciandi, J.C., Castro-Tejerina, J. The Clay of Evolution: Megalomania in (Evolutionary) Psychology. Integr. psych. behav. 56, 297–307 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-020-09584-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-020-09584-7

Keywords

Navigation