Abstract
This article is an attempt to reply to a number of theoretical and epistemological issues frequently addressed in contemporary evolutionary psychology. We adopt a critical approach to both the empiricist conceit so often underlying the discipline and its core premises around the relationship between mind and biological evolution. As an alternative we take a constructivist view from which we propose to broach that relationship through the so-called Baldwin effect. That phenomenon, widely known among evolutionary biologists today, enables us to elude simplistic approaches to the problem of the relationship between psychology and evolution. It also affords a perspective for re-focusing the issues on the activity of organisms and the classic inter-connections among phylogenesis, historiogenesis and ontogenesis. The study concludes with a warning about the limitations to explanation that should be assumed by any psychological postulate with universally comprehensive pretensions, an issue evocative of the inevitable and structural crisis in which psychology should agree to transpire.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
‘Tradition’ insofar as texts on the discipline’s crisis can be found in the late nineteenth to early twentieth century institutional ‘foundation’ of scientific psychology, a circumstance that has led to a proposal for a specific bibliographic genre (Blanco 2002). The authors who first addressed the crisis would include, for instance, Willy in 1897, Gutberlet in 1898, Stern in 1900, Kostilff in 1911 and Bühler and Vigotsky, both in 1927. Although not overly prevalent in the literature, texts and monographs on the crisis have periodically dotted the editorial landscape and even revisited more classic studies (Caparrós 1991; VV.AA. 2006; Sturm and Mülberger 2012; Wieser 2016). The question that may be posed, then, is whether such a belaboured crisis is more an opportunity than a stumbling block for psychology; or as Blanco (2002) perceptively asked, whether the history of the crisis of psychology is rather a history of the successive crises affecting western subjectivity from the Modern Age to date. That hypothesis will echo throughout the considerations with which we conclude this article.
Deeming biological to be more material than psychological reality is bias because the body is only more real than the mind in the (trivial) sense that its existence is bound to what we perceive as a touchable shape, something that takes up space. Unless we believe in immaterial reality, however, any manner of existence is tied to practice and objects, material things (Bueno 1990; Coole and Frost 2010; Fox and Alldred 2019). Some dimensions of the body are not phenomenic but conceptual (or phenomenic only through devices such as microscopes or mathematical formulae): our neurons, not to mention bodily motion or biomechanics, are cases in point.
Whilst the authors mention, albeit only in passing, that ‘the brain and the body are directly affected by the mind itself, which operates as a “social organ” that converts relational experiences in the brain and somatic processes’ (p. 2), they draw no theoretical implication from that assertion. The idea that the mind is a social organ, as we shall suggest later, can be readily reintegrated into a theoretical evolutionary-psychological structure that reverts to the starting point: biological reality on the one hand and psychological reality, fruit of the former, on the other.
Zagaria, Andò and Zennaro’s epistemic choices are not aseptic when identifying valid representatives: rather they entail visibilising certain psychological tendencies (such as psychoanalysis, cognitivism and neuroscience) and invisibilising others (cultural, genetic, ecological psychology, to name a few). The same can be said of the epistemological structure proposed, where they opt ‘naturally’ for certain conceits (using the Kuhnian idea of paradigm, for instance) over others. As we have been contending all along, no choice is devoid of values and commitments, no matter how objective it may claim to be.
The authors of the article mention epigenetic premises (marginally) (‘[e]pigenetic variations are comprehended as well, because it is demonstrated that they are hereditable and can be selected in the evolution process’, p. 15), while asserting that the gene is widely accepted as the unit of selection, a contention scantly compatible with epigenetic interpretations.
References
Baldwin, J. M. (1896). A new factor in evolution. The American Naturalist, 30, 441–451 536-553.
Baldwin, J. M. (1917). Development and evolution (2nd ed.). New York: Macmillan.
Baltes, P. B., Reuter-Lorenz, P. A., & Rösler, F. (Eds.). (2006). Lifespan development and the brain. The perspective of biocultural co-constructivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blanco, F. (2002). El cultivo de la mente. Un ensayo histórico-critico sobre la cultura psicológica. Madrid: Antonio Machado.
Boakes, R. A. (1984). From Darwin to Behaviourism. Psychology and the mind of Animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bowler, P. J. (1983). The eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian evolutionary theories in the decades around 1900. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
Brown, H. I. (1977). Perception. Theory and Commitment. The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Bueno, G. (1990). Materia. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Cairns, R. B. (1991). Multiple metaphors for a singular idea. Developmental Psychology, 27(1), 23–26.
Caparrós, A. (1991). Crisis de la psicología: ¿singular o plural? Aproximación a algo más que un concepto historiografico. Anuario de Psicologia, 51, 5–20.
Castro, J., & Loredo, J. C. (2015). Evolution, activity and assembled mediation: A neo-Baldwinian response to the universalism of evolutionary psychology. Culture & Psychology, 21(1), 111–123.
Castro, J., & Loredo, J. C. (2018). Psytizenship: Sociocultural mediations in the historical shaping of western citizen. In A. Rosa & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 479–500). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Coole, D., & Frost, S. (Eds.). (2010). New materialisms: Ontology, agency and politics. Durham: Duke University Press.
Deacon, T. W. (1997). The symbolic specie. The co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Dekker, T. M., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2011). The dynamics of ontogeny: A Neuroconstructivist perspective on genes, brains, cognition and behavior. Progress in Brain Research, 189, 23–33.
Edelman, G. (1987). Neural Darwinism: The theory of neuronal group selection. New York: Basic Books.
Fox, N. J., & Alldred, P. (2019). New materialism. In P. A. Atkinson, S. Delamont, A. Cernat, J. W. Sakshaug, & M. Williams (Eds.), SAGE research methods foundations. London: Sage.
Franks, B. (2014). Social construction, evolution and cultural universals. Culture & Psychology, 20(3), 416–439.
Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hinton, G. E., & Nowlan, S. J. (1987). How learning can guide evolution. Complex Systems, 1, 495–502.
Huxley, J. S. (1942). Evolution. The modern synthesis. New York: Harper.
Ingold, T. (2013). Prospect. In T. Ingold & G. Palsson (Eds.), Biosocial Becomings: Integrating social and biological anthropology (pp. 1–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (1995). Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: The Lamarckian dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kull, K. (2000). Organisms can be proud to be their own designers. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 7(1), 45–55.
Loredo, J. C. (2019). Psychology as a technique of Subjectivation. Papeles del Psicólogo, 40(1), 31–38 http://www.papelesdelpsicologo.es/ico/pdf_ico.png.
Loy, I., Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1992). El funcionalismo en perspectiva. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 13(2–3), 197–206.
Maynard-Smith, J. (1987). When learning guides evolution. Nature, 329(29), 761–762.
Maynard-Smith, J. (1998). Shaping life. Genes, embryos and evolution. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Moore, C. (2003). Evolution, development, and the individual Acquisition of Traits: What We’ve learned since Baldwin. In B. H. Weber & D. J. Depew (Eds.), Evolution and learning. The Baldwin effect reconsidered (pp. 115–139). Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Moreno, J. (2008). Los retos actuales del darwinismo. ¿Una teoría en crisis? [The current challenges of Darwinism. A theory in crisis? ]. Madrid: Síntesis.
Oyama, S. (2000). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution (2ª ed.). Durham: Duke University Press.
Pérez, M. (2011). El Mito del cerebro creador. Cuerpo, cultura y conducta. Madrid: Alianza.
Pérez, M. (2018). Thinking psychology beyond the mind and the brain: A trans-theoretical approach. Papeles del Psicólogo, 39(3), 161–173 http://www.papelesdelpsicologo.es/English/2875.pdf.
Quartz, S. R., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development. A constructivist manifesto. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 537–556.
Ramírez, E. (2013). Life-in-the-making: Epigenesis, biocultural environments and human Becomings. In T. Ingold & G. Palsson (Eds.), Biosocial Becomings: Integrating social and biological anthropology (pp. 59–83). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Richards, R. J. (1987). Darwin and the evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sampedro, J. (2013). Deconstruyendo a Darwin. Los enigmas de la evolución a través de la nueva genética. Barcelona: Planeta.
Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990a). James, la selección natural y el funcionalismo. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 41–52.
Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990b). Funcionalismo y teoría de la selección orgánica. Revisión de algunos problemas conceptuales en el origen de la psicología comparada. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 53–66.
Sánchez, J. C., & Fernández, T. R. (1990c). Reconsideración histórica de la selección natural. Revista de Historia de la Psicología, 11(3–4), 517–528.
Sánchez, J. C., & Loredo, J. C. (2007). In circles we go. Baldwin’s theory of organic selection and its current uses: A constructivist view. Theory & Psychology, 17(1), 33–58.
Sánchez, J. C., & Loredo, J. C. (2009). Constructivisms from a genetic point of view. A critical classification of current tendencies. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 43(4), 332–349.
Scott, J. (2004). Embryology, Epigenesis and evolution. Taking Development Seriously. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sturm, T., & Mülberger, A. (2012). Crisis discussions in psychology. New historical and philosophical perspectivas. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(2), 425–433.
Turney, P., & Whytley, D. (1996). Evolution, learning and instinct: 100 years of the Baldwin effect. Evolutionay Computation, 4(3), v-viii.
VV.AA. (2006). La crisis de la psicología. Anuario de Psicología, 37(1–2).
Vygotsky, L. S. (1997). The historical meaning of the crisis of psychology. In R. Rieber, & J. Wolloc (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (pp. 233–344). New York, London: Plenum Press.
Weber, B. H., & Depew, D. J. (Eds.). (2003a). Evolution and learning. The Baldwin effect reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Weber, B., & Depew, D. (Eds.). (2003b). Learning, meaning and emergence: Possible Baldwinian mechanisms for evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.
West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wieser, M. (2016). Psychology’s “crisis” and the need for reflection. A Plea for modesty in psychological theorizing. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Sciences, 50(3), 359–367.
Zagaria, A., Andò, A., & Zennaro, A. (2020). Psychology: a Giant with Feet of Clay. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 54(3), 521–562.
Funding
This study was not funded.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of Interest
José Carlos Loredo-Narciandi declares that he has no conflict of interest. Jorge Castro-Tejerina declares that he has no conflict of interest.
Ethical Approval
This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Loredo-Narciandi, J.C., Castro-Tejerina, J. The Clay of Evolution: Megalomania in (Evolutionary) Psychology. Integr. psych. behav. 56, 297–307 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-020-09584-7
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-020-09584-7