Skip to main content
Log in

The Solipsism of Pornography: Speech Act Theory and the Anti-Porn Position

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Sexuality & Culture Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present essay takes as its point of departure the resurgence of the anti-porn argument claiming that pornography is harmful. It focuses especially on philosopher Rae Langton’s attempt to use speech act theory to defend the anti-porn position of Catherine MacKinnon. Langton’s argument is critiqued for assuming that we can ascertain the function of pornography without considering the situations of its use. It hence runs counter to the particularizing intent of speech act theory as such, which emphasizes the need to study speech in context. Rather than dismiss the anti-porn position Langton defends as faulty, the essay suggests that it remains an incontrovertible facet of the pornographic situation, and as such should be dialectically engaged. In the second half of the essay, therefore, the reasoning that informs the antiporn position is shown to be incompatible with the recurrent claim that porn is the expression of a male desire to dominate women. Rather, a closer look at Langton’s defense of the anti-porn argument helps us see that pornography is the expression of cognitive possibilities unique to the historical conditions that have brought it forth, and as such is every bit as self-conflicting as is capitalism itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Subsequently, this source will be cited in the text without name and date.

  2. In the introduction to Porn Studies, Williams (2004) simply shirks the issue of pornography’s alleged harmfulness, on the grounds that for her students it is a non-issue. For a succinct overview of the new paradigm in porn studies, see Attwood (2002).

  3. For background and details on the ordinance, see MacKinnon and Dworkin (1997).

  4. John L. Austin (1911–1960) was Professor of Moral Philosophy at Oxford University. In 1955, he delivered the James Lectures at Harvard, which subsequently formed the basis for his most important work, How to do things with words (1962). In it, Austin advocates the examination of the way words are ordinarily used in order to elucidate meaning and by this means to avoid philosophical confusions.

  5. Langton was to my knowledge the first person to take a speech act perspective on pornography, but several critics have followed suit; see Hornsby (1995). McGowan, likewise, follows Langton not only in arguing that pornography is a speech act, but in taking MacKinnon’s definition of pornography as given, yet claiming that she is “not interested in arguing for the truth of MacKinnon’s constructionist claims,” but aims “only to show both that and how her claims could be true” (McGowan 2005, 23). She goes on to distinguish between “Macpornography” and pornography on the grounds that MacKinnon’s definition of pornography as “the graphic sexually explicit subordination of women, whether in pictures or in words” departs from the standard understanding of the term. This is spurious, however, since MacKinnon has repeatedly made clear that in her view all pornography subordinates women. West does not rely on speech act theory, but echoes Langton in claiming that she “will not be defending the claim that consumption of pornography does in fact silence women in the requisite way, and so in fact violates women’s right to free speech. For that is an issue that cannot be decided a priori from the philosopher’s armchair” (West 2003, 3). Wieland (2007), in contrast, expands Langton’s argument by providing an account of how pornography may be said to have authority, but rejects her argument on the grounds that it leads to intolerable results. Saul (2006) critiques Langton along lines similar to those suggested in this article, namely that it does not make sense to view pornography as speech acts without considering the context of its use; Bianchi (2008) in turn critiques Saul’s critique; Mikkola (2008), finally, makes short thrift of Bianchi. See also note 8 below.

  6. Langton’s exchange with Jacobson (1995) makes evident that she is aware of Strawson’s view but dismisses it because Jacobson claims his argument in no way depends upon Strawson’s account (see Langton 2009, 82). But even if Jacobson is wrong to suggest that he can counter Langton’s reasoning independently of Strawson, surely Langton ought to register that Strawson’s explication of Austin—it is notably not an interpretation—renders her argument null and void independently of Jacobson’s argument.

  7. For a discussion of pornography and the First Amendment conception of free speech, see Koppelman (2008).

  8. These objections are not new, indeed, Sexual solipsism is to a considerable extent composed of essays that respond to critiques of her original discussion of the issue. Ronald Dworkin dismissed MacKinnon’s argument that pornography silences women on the grounds that it “is premised on an unacceptable proposition: that the right to free speech includes a right to circumstances that encourage one to speak, and a right that others grasp and respect what one means to say” (Dworkin 1993, 38). Dworkin's article is a review of MacKinnon's Only Words. He also maintains that the argument that pornography is harmful is unconvincing, and that therefore the claim that pornography subordinates women if true can only be true in a weak sense, and thus is offset by the counterargument “that everyone has an equal right to contribute to what I called the ‘moral environment’—even people whose tastes reflect no ‘ideas’ but only very offensive ‘prejudices, life styles, and cultures’” (MacKinnon and Dworkin 1994, 48). Jacobson (1995) grants that Langton’s “explication of the silencing argument succeeds in making MacKinnon's claim both literal and coherent,” but objects that it does so only “at the cost of defensibility” (67). According to Jacobson, Langton confuses illocutionary disablement with perlocutionary frustration, or to put it in less technical terms, she fails to distinguish between the inability to perform the act of refusing, and the fact of not being listened to. Leslie Green grants that it is not inconceivable that pornography could silence and subordinate women, but contests Langton’s claim that pornographers have the sort of authority necessary to do so, and suggests “that illocutionary disablement does not in itself amount to an objectionable kind of silencing” (Green 1998, 303). More broadly, he objects to Langton on the grounds that pornography is not a monolithic entity, and as discourse is simply not conventional enough to be the object of speech act theory (Green 1998, 304–305). Judith Butler, finally, who has done a great deal herself to highlight the performative dimension of language, rejects MacKinnon’s notion that pornography subordinates women on the grounds that MacKinnon wrongfully transposes the predominantly visual register of pornography into a linguistic register, even into “an efficacious performative” (Butler 1997, 67) that is, into a speech act which is somehow always felicitous, regardless of situation. In effect, then, MacKinnon’s argument presupposes that pornography has the authority of a divine subject, who always gets its will. Furthermore, in arguing that pornography violates women’s rights in recontextualizing their intended meanings, MacKinnon and Langton alike fail to register that such recontextualizations of utterances can also be—and has historically been—a source of empowerment (Butler 1997, 92–95).

  9. Langton is citing American Booksellers Inc. v. Hudnut, 771 F2d 329 (7th Cir. 1985).

  10. The footnote reads in full (with emphasis added by Dworkin): “MacKinnon’s article collects empirical work that supports this proposition. The social science studies are very difficult to interpret, however, and they conflict. Because much of the effect of speech comes through a process of socialization, it is difficult to measure incremental benefits and injuries caused by particular speech. Several psychologists have found, for example, that those who see violent, sexually explicit films tend to have more violent thoughts. But how often does this lead to actual violence? National commissions on obscenity here, in the United Kingdom, and in Canada have found that it is not possible to demonstrate a direct link between obscenity and rape or exhibitionism. The several opinions in Miller v. California discuss the US commission. See also Report of the Committee on Obscenity and Film Censorship 61–95 (Home Office, Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1979); Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution, 1 Pornography and Prostitution in Canada 71–73, 95–103 (Canadian Government Publishing Centre 1985). In saying that we accept the finding that pornography as the ordinance defines it leads to unhappy consequences, we mean only that there is evidence to this effect, that this evidence is consistent with much human experience, and that as judges we must accept the legislative resolution of such disputed empirical questions. See Gregg v. Georgia, 428 US 153, 184–87, 49 L. Ed. 2d 859, 96 S. Ct. 2909 (1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and Stevens, J.J.).”

  11. In a footnote she also advances Andrea Dworkin’s description of a photograph and caption in Hustler (Langton 2009, 138 n64).

  12. When the claim is repeated at later points in the argument, Langton says that she “received in her junk mail a catalogue of pornographic material in which Ordeal was marketed as pornography” (188); “It was marketed that way in junk mail I once received” (263).

  13. Contrary to the majority of gay and lesbian critics, Kendall argues that there are no grounds for distinguishing between gay male porn and heterosexual porn in this context. Langton, for her part, simply ignores the challenge that same-sex pornography poses to the argument that pornography is essentially misogynist, despite the fact that critics like Waugh (1995), Burger (1995), Dyer (1998), Champagne (1997), Cante and Restivo (2004) and many others adamantly and eloquently argue otherwise.

  14. Beyond the laboratory studies referred to below, see for instance Russell (1998), and MacKinnon and Dworkin (1997).

  15. See Athanasiou (1993), Carol (1994), Christensen (1986), King (1993), McCormack (1978), McKay and Dolff (1985), Pally (1994), 25–61, and Segal (1993). For an overview of pornography effects studies, see Slade (2001). For a cogent general critique of effects studies, see Gauntlet (1998).

  16. She fails to report that this article is a response to and critique of Fisher and Grenier (1994), who argue that porn effect studies commonly do not show what they claim to show.

  17. On a more generous reading, Langton when speaking about pornography could be taken to talk not about pornography in general, but merely a particular subset of pornography, namely that which causes harm. Thus Roadevin (2010) argues that “Langton uses a revisionary definition of pornography which is different from the one we usually use.” In Roadevin’s view this entails that it is therefore “no criticism of Langton to say that pornography usually is not like this or that we do not use the term in this way” (76). Notwithstanding the fact that this leaves the issue of how “harm” is to be defined unaddressed and fails to consider whether one can plausibly assume that such harm may not come with compensatory effects (drilling for oil causes harm to nature, but it comes with compensatory effects of a wide array), one need but substitute for “pornography” some other general category to realize how problematic this line of reasoning is. If (some) Russians are rapists, is there cause to enforce laws against (all) Russians?

  18. Paul notably does not account for her methodology, but claims that she bases her contention on the evidence of a study conducted by Bryant and Zillman (1982) some three decades ago, which was thoroughly criticized already on its original publication. She refers to the study as “a landmark experiment conducted 25 years ago—still one of the most thorough, balanced, and powerful studies on pornography” and claims it shows “just how watching pornography alters viewers’ perceptions of sexuality” (Paul 2005, 77). She fails to mention that the study has been severely critiqued, that other researchers have failed to repeat its results (Donnerstein et al. 1987), and that non-laboratory studies have come to the opposite conclusion. Davies (1997) found no correlations between the number of pornographic videos a man had rented and his attitudes toward feminism and rape, and argues that her findings suggest that calloused attitudes toward women may not be generated by sexually explicit videos but are more deeply ingrained in our society. For a critique of Bryant and Zillmann’s experimental work, see Brannigan (1987); and Christensen (1986); for their replies, see Bryant and Zillmann (1986, 1987). On a more general level, the difficulties with using experimental methods to establish a link between pornography use and violence towards women are discussed by Childress (1991), who lists (1) the unreal nature of lab violence, (2) lack of real punishment or social control, (3) respondents' inhibitions while being observed or interviewed, (4) the use of willing college students as the norm, (5). an experimenter demand effect, (6) publication of studies, mainly if they have positive results, (7) lack of precise definitions of violence and aggression, and (8) the ethical inability to produce real violence as factors compromising the results of such works.

  19. For testimony to a similar effect, see for instance Kimmel (1989).

  20. For Todd, see Barker-Benfield (2000); for Bowdler, see Perrin (1970).

  21. For the relation between pornography and masturbation, in addition to the below discussion see Ullén (2009) and Garlick (2012).

  22. For an important and nuanced counter-statement to the notion that women have little taste in pornography, see Smith (2007). It is true that Playgirl’s readership includes gay men, yet according to editor Nicole Caldwell, Playgirl’s own statistics suggest its “readers are 60 % female, 40 % male” (e-mail to the author, 2008-05-06).

  23. For evidence of the cultural specificity of same-sex pornography, see for instance Thomas (2000), Morrison and Tallack (2005), and the sources listed in note 13 above.

  24. For a more elaborate argument to the same effect, see Bersani (2010).

References

  • Allen, M., Emmers, T. M., Gebhardt, L., & Giery, M. (1995). Pornography and rape myth acceptance. Journal of Communication, 45, 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Athanasiou, R. (1993). Pornography: A review of research. In B. B. Wolman & J. Money (Eds.), Handbook of human sexuality (pp. 251–268). Northvale: Aronson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Attwood, F. (2002). Reading porn: The paradigm shift in pornography research. Sexualities, 5(1), 91–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). In J. O. Urmson & M. Sbisà (Eds.), How to do things with words: The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955. Oxford: Clarendon.

  • Barker-Benfield, G. J. (2000). The horrors of the half-known life: Male attitudes toward women and sexuality in nineteenth-century America. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bersani, L. (2010). Is the rectum a grave? and other essays. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, C. (2008). Indexicals, speech acts and pornography. Analysis, 68(300), 310–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brannigan, A. (1987). Pornography and behavior: Alternative explanations. Journal of Communication, 37, 185–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, J., & Zillman, D. (1982). Pornography and sexual callousness, and the trivialization of rape. Journal of Communication, 32, 10–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, J., & Zillman, D. (1986). Sexual callousness re-examined, a reply. Journal of Communication, 36, 184–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, J., & Zillman, D. (1987). Pornography and behavior: alternative explanations, a reply. Journal of Communication, 37, 189–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burger, J. R. (1995). One-handed histories: The eroto-politics of gay male video pornography. New York: Haworth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, K. (1973). The philosophy of literary form: Studies in symbolic action (3rd ed.). Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1997). Excitable speech: A politics of the performative. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cante, R., & Restivo, A. (2004). The cultural-aesthetic specificities of all-male moving-image pornography. In L. Williams (Ed.), Porn studies (pp. 142–166). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carol, A. (1994). Nudes, prudes, and attitudes. Cheltenham: New Clarion Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, J. (1997). “Stop reading films!” Film studies, close analysis, and gay pornography. Cinema Journal, 36(4), 76–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Childress, S. A. (1991). Reel “rape speech”: Violent pornography and the politics of harm. Law and Society Review, 25, 177–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, F. M. (1986). Sexual callousness reexamined. Journal of Communication, 36(1), 174–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, K. A. (1997). Voluntary exposure to pornography and men’s attitudes toward feminism and rape. Journal of Sex Research, 34, 131–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnerstein, E., Linz, D., & Penrod, S. (1987). The question of pornography: Research findings and policy implications. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1993). Women and pornography. The New York Review of Books, 40 (16), 21 October, 36–42.

  • Dyer, R. (1998). Idol thoughts: Orgasm and self-reflexivity in gay pornography. In N. Mirzoeff (Ed.), The visual culture reader (pp. 504–515). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, W. A., & Grenier, G. (1994). Violent pornography, antiwoman thoughts, and antiwoman acts: in search of reliable effects. The Journal of Sex Research, 31, 23–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foxon, David. (1965). Libertine literature in England 1660–1745. New York: University Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garlick, S. (2012). Masculinity, pornography, and the history of masturbation. Sexuality and Culture, 16(3), 306–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauntlet, D. (1998). Ten things wrong with the media “effects” model. In R. Dickinson, R. Harindranath, & O. Linné (Eds.), Approaches to audiences: A reader. London: Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulemout, J. M. (1994). Forbidden texts: Erotic literature and its readers in eighteenth-century France (J. Simpson, Trans). Philadelphia: University of Philadelphia Press.

  • Green, L. (1998). Pornographizing, subordinating, silencing. In R. Post (Ed.), Censorship and silencing: Practices of cultural regulation (pp. 285–311). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1995). Speech acts and pornography. In S. Dwyer (Ed.), The problem of pornography (pp. 220–232). Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Itzin, C. (1992). ‘Entertainment for men’: What it is and what it means. In C. Itzin (Ed.), Pornography: Women, violence and civil liberties (pp. 27–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, D. (1995). Freedom of speech acts? A response to Langton. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 24(1), 64–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, R. (2007). Getting off: Pornography and the end of masculinity. Cambridge: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendall, C. N. (2004). Gay male pornography: An issue of sex discrimination. Vancouver: UBC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendrick, W. (1987). The secret museum: Pornography in modern culture. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimmel, M. (Ed.). (1989). Men confront pornography. New York: Crown.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, A. (1993). Mystery and imagination: The case of pornography effects studies. In A. Assiter & A. Carol (Eds.), Bad girls & dirty pictures: The challenge to reclaim feminism (pp. 57–87). London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koppelman, A. (2008). Is pornography ‘speech’? Legal Theory, 14(1), 71–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2009). Sexual solipsism: Philosophical essays on pornography and objectification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laqueur, T. (2003). Solitary sex: A cultural history of masturbation. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2007). Foreword. In A. Dworkin, Intercourse: The twentieth anniversary edition (pp. xi–xxvii). New York: Basic Books.

  • Lovelace, L., with McGrady, M. (1981). Ordeal. London: W. H. Allen.

  • MacKinnon, C. A. (1987). Feminism unmodified: Discourses on life and law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, C. A., & Dworkin, A. (Eds.). (1997). In harm’s way: The pornography civil rights hearings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, C. A., with a reply by Dworkin, R. (1994). Pornography: An exchange. The New York Review of Books, 41 (5), March 3, 47–49.

  • Malamuth, N. M., Addison, T., & Koss, M. (2000). Pornography and sexual aggression: Are there reliable effects and can we understand them? Annual Review of Sex Research, 11, 26–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T. (1978). Machismo in media research: A critical review of research on violence and pornography. Social Problems, 25(5), 544–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGowan, M. K. (2005). On pornography: MacKinnon, speech acts, and ‘false’ construction. Hypatia, 20(3), 22–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGregor, S. (1989). Rape, pornography and capitalism. International Socialism, 45(2), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, H. B., & Dolff, D. J. (1985). The impact of pornography: An analysis of research and summary of findings. Working Papers on Pornography and Prostitution: Report 13. Ottawa: Federal Department of Justice.

  • McKee, A., Albury, K., & Lumby, C. (2008). The porn report. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkola, M. (2008). Contexts and pornography. Analysis, 68(300), 316–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, T. G., & Tallack, D. (2005). Lesbian and bisexual women’s interpretations of lesbian and ersatz lesbian pornography. Sexuality and Culture, 9(2), 3–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palac, L. (1998). The edge of the bed: How dirty pictures changed my life. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pally, M. (1994). Sex and sensibility: Reflections on forbidden mirrors and the will to censor. Hopewell: Ecco Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, P. (2005). Pornified: How pornography is transforming our lives, our relationships, our families. New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrin, N. (1970). Dr. Bowdler’s legacy: A history of expurgated books in England and America. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roadevin, C. (2010). Review of Rae Langton, sexual solipsism. Disputatio, 4(29), 75–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. E. H. (1998). Dangerous relationships: Pornography, misogyny, and rape. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarracino, C., & Scott, K. M. (2008). The porning of America: The rise of porn culture, what it means, and where we go from here. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2006). Pornography, speech acts, and context. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106(2), 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scruton, R. (2006). A political philosophy: Arguments for conservatism. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, L. (1993). Does pornography cause violence? The search for evidence. In P. Church Gibson & R. Gibson (Eds.), Dirty looks: Women, pornography, power (pp. 5–21). London: British Film Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slade, J. W. (Ed.). (2001). Research on pornography in the medical and social sciences. Pornography and sexual representation: A reference guide, Volume III (pp. 954–1017). Westport: Greenwood Press.

  • Smith, C. (2007). One for the girls: The pleasures and practices of reading women’s porn. Bristol: Intellect.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sohn, A. (2005). Pornified: Dirty minds. New York Times, September 11.

  • Sohn-Rethel, A. (1978). Intellectual and manual labour. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1964). Intention and convention in speech acts. Philosophical Review, 73, 439–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, J. A. (2000). Gay male video pornography: Past, present, and future. In R. Weitzer (Ed.), Sex for sale: Prostitution, pornography, and the sex industry (pp. 49–66). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. G. (2003). Schooling sex: Libertine literature and erotic education in Italy, France, and England 1534–1685. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ullén, M. (2009). Pornography and its critical reception: Toward a theory of masturbation. Jump Cut, 51.

  • Waugh, T. (1995). Men’s pornography: Gay vs. straight. In C. K. Creekmur & A. Doty (Eds.), Out in culture: Gay, lesbian, and queer essays on popular culture (pp. 307–327). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, C. (2003). The free speech argument against pornography. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(3), 391–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, N. (2007). Linguistic authority and convention in a speech act analysis of pornography. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(3), 435–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, L. (2004). Porn studies. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zizek, S. (2008). The sublime object of ideology. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Magnus Ullén.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ullén, M. The Solipsism of Pornography: Speech Act Theory and the Anti-Porn Position. Sexuality & Culture 17, 321–347 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12119-012-9154-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12119-012-9154-1

Keywords

Navigation