Skip to main content
Log in

Exploitation and Efficiency

  • Published:
The Review of Black Political Economy

Abstract

Let us take any historical or contemporary economic society. Would economic efficiency become better if such society erects and enforces institutions that prohibit its members from the exploitation of excludable groups that can be defined by race, ethnicity, etc.? This question actually makes no sense. One must first identity the boundary of society, i.e., who make up the objective function. Irrespective of how one defines efficiency, one cannot assess the efficiency of institutions without determining who is covered and who is excluded. Efficiency judgments can make sense only when one defines the social boundary.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An additional possible target of Ogilvie’s critique is Fogel and Engerman’s (1974) thesis that the institution of slavery in the American South was efficient.

  2. Given the exploitative nature of the monopoly restrictions, exploited segments can try to escape the exploitation by engaging in informal economies. Such shadow economies are usually illegal. This imposes high transaction costs on their participants— such as the jailing of people of color for drug “crimes” in the USA—and hence forms the basis for another round of exploitative practices against the weaker segments of society.

  3. Both true externalities and pecuniary externalities can be positive or negative. So, this is not the issue. Following Ogilvie, we restrict the usage of the term to denote only “negative externality.”

  4. To recall, an event invokes a pecuniary externality when, under complete markets, the consequent loss fully offsets the consequent gain. The consequences of the event worked its way, unhindered, through the market via the price system and, hence, the outcome is Pareto efficient as expressed in the First Theorem of Welfare Economics (Mas-Colell et al. 1995, ch. 16). In contrast, an event involves a real externality (i.e., negative real externality) when the price system fails to capture the full cost of production. Part of the cost is born by neighbors or people downstream who are not fully compensated and, hence, the outcome is Pareto inefficient.

  5. Ng (2007) faults Coase Theorem for being either/or. Ng convincingly argues that pollution, or in our example, the height of the wall, can be of different degrees. As such there is an asymmetry of harm: an incremental increase of the harmful activity is very costly to the injured but an incremental decrease of the activity would be of little cost to the violator. So, Ng, argues it pays to apply Pigouvian taxes, adjusted to the extent of the pollution, rather than a lump-sum penalty as implied by Coase Theorem. There are many other issues, such as transaction costs, which need not concern us here.

  6. Given Ogilvie’s rendition, it would be impossible for a side-payment to eliminate exploitation. In order to fully compensate the exploiter while raising the wellbeing of the exploitee to the same level as the insiders’ wellbeing, the exploitee would have to side-pay the exploiter the full amount that the exploitee would gain from the elimination of exploitation. That is, there is no raison d’être to expand the boundary and eliminate exploitation; the elimination would be zero-sum.

References

  • Arrow KJ. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley; 1951.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ. Social Choice and Individual Values. 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale University Press; 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS. A theory of competition among pressure groups for political influence. Q J Econ. 1983;98:371–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergson A. A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. Q J Econ. 1938;52:310–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergson A. On the concept of social welfare. Q J Econ. 1954;68:232–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby C, Donaldson D. A review article: The case against the use of the sum of compensating variations in cost-benefit analysis. Can J Econ. 1990;23:471–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coase R. The problem of social cost. J Law Econ. 1960;3:1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz H. The problem of social cost: What problem? A critique of the reasoning of A.C. Pigou and R.H. Coase. Rev Law Econ. 2011;7(1):1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogel RW, Engerman SL. Time on the Cross, vol. 2. Boston: Little, Brown; 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald B, Stiglitz J. Externalities in economies with imperfect information and incomplete markets. Q J Econ. 1986;101:229–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi JC. Utilities, preferences, and substantive goods. Soc Choice Welf. 1997;14:129–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks J. The Foundations of Welfare Economics. Econ J. 1939;49:696–712. https://doi.org/10.2307/2225023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor N. Welfare Propositions in Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility. Econ J. 1939;49:549–52. https://doi.org/10.2307/2224835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemp MC, Ng Y-K. On the existence of social welfare functions: Social orderings and social decision functions. Economica. 1976;43:59–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemp MC, Ng Y-K. Individualistic social welfare functions under ordinalism: A reply to Mayston. Math Soc Sci. 1983;4:305–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalil EL. Rationality and social labor in Marx. Crit Rev. 1990;4:239–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalil EL. The implication for socialism of Marx's theory of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall. J Hist Econ Thought. 1994;16:292–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalil EL. What Determines the Boundary of Civil Society? Hume, Smith and the Justification of European Exploitation of non-Europeans. Theoria. 2013;59:26–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalil EL. Distinguishing Injustice, Exploitation and Harm: The Impossibility Result. Theoria. 2017;64:24–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger A. The political economy of the rent-seeking society. Am Econ Rev. 1974;64:291–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. Capital, vol. 1, intro. by Ernest Mandel. Harmondsworth: Penguin; London: New Left Books; 1976.

  • Mas-Colell A, Whinston M, Green JR. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell W. Doing well while intending good: Cases in political exploitation. J Theor Politics. 1993;5:317–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ng Y-K. Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. Biol Philos. 1995;10:255–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ng Y-K. Utility, informed preference, or happiness: Following Harsanyi’s argument to its logical conclusion. Soc Choice Welf. 1999;16:197–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ng Y-K. Eternal Coase and external costs: A case for bilateral taxation and amenity rights. Eur J Polit Econ. 2007;23:641–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North D, Thomas R. The Rise of the Western World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1973.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • North D, Wallis J, Weingast B. Violence and Social Orders: A Conceptual Framework for Interpreting Recorded Human History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2009.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogilvie S. ‘Whatever is, is right?’ Economic institutions in pre-industrial Europe. Econ Hist Rev. 2007;60:649–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ogilvie S. Institutions and European Trade. Merchant Guilds, 1000–1800. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2011.

  • Posner RA. Utilitarianism, economics, and legal theory. J Leg Stud. 1979;8:103–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA. Economic Analysis of Law. 7th ed. Austin: Kluwer; 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1947.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA. Reaffirming the existence of ‘reasonable’ Bergson-Samuelson social welfare functions. Economica. New Ser. 1977;44:81–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK. Social choice theory: A re-examination. Econometrica. 1977;45:53–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK. Development as Freedom. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK. The Idea of Justice. London: Allen Lane; 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer P. Animal Liberation. New York: Ecco; 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock G. The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Econ J. 1967;5:224–32.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions benefited from comments of participants at the Korea Institution and Economics Association meeting, Alan Wertheimer, Nichloas Feltovich, Alain Marciano, Yew-Kwang Ng, Michael Niekamp, John Thrasher, Deirdre McCloskey, Bart Nooteboom, Harold Jones, Ian McDonald, Gary Magee, and anonymous referees. The usual caveat applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elias L. Khalil.

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Khalil, E.L. Exploitation and Efficiency. Rev Black Polit Econ 44, 363–377 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12114-017-9263-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12114-017-9263-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation