Advertisement

Science and Engineering Ethics

, Volume 5, Issue 4, pp 531–540 | Cite as

Why be my colleague’s keeper? Moral justifications for peer review

  • Joe CainEmail author
Article

Abstract

Justifying ethical practices is no easy task. This paper considers moral justifications for peer review so as to persuade even the sceptical individualist. Two avenues provide a foundation for that justification: self-interest (the right behaviour is that which maximally serves one’s own interests) and social contract theory (the right behaviour is that which best meets obligations set in binding social contracts). A wider notion of “interest” permits the self-interest approach to justify not only submitting one’s own work to peer review but also removing oneself momentarily from the production of primary knowledge to serve as a rigorous, independent, and honest referee. The contract approach offers a non-selfish alternative and relies on four types of binding social contracts: those implicit in accepting funds, those implicit in asserted professional status, those to contribute what is of most value to society, and those to defend the ideals of the Academy. Efforts to restore respect for rigorous, independent, honest peer review should begin in earnest.

Keywords

peer review social contract individualism moral economy of science 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Rachels, J. (1993) The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 2nd ed., McGraw Hill, New York.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Thomson, A. (1996) Critical Reasoning: A Practical Guide, Routledge, New York.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Kohler, R. (1994) Lords of the Fly: Drosophila Genetics and the Experimental Control of Life, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Harcum, E. and Rosen, E. (1993) The Gatekeepers of Psychology: Evaluation of Peer Review by Case History, Praeger, Westport, CT.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Traweek, S. (1988) Beamtimes and Lifetimes: the World of High energy Physicists, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Hull, D. (1988) Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Rudwick, M.J.S. (1985) The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Knowledge among Gentlemanly Specialists, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Stewart, W. and Feder, N. (1987) The Integrity of the Scientific Literature. Nature 325 (15 January): 207–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Resnik, D. (1998), The Ethics of Science, Routledge, New York.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Stamps III, A. E., editor. (1997) Advances in Peer Review Research, special issue of Science and Engineering Ethics 3(1): 3–98.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Speek, B., ed. (1993) Publication Peer Review: An Annotated Bibliography, Greenwood Press, Westport, CT.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Chubin, D. (1990) Peerless Science: Peer Review and US Science Policy, SUNY Press, Albany, NY.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Sober, E. (1993) Philosophy of Biology, Westview, Boulder, CO.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Rousseau, J.-J. (1762) The Social Contract, translated by M. Cranston (1968), Penguin Books, New York.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Krohn, W. and Layton, E., eds. (1978) The Dynamics of Science and Technology: Social Values, Technical Norms, and Scientific Criteria in the Development of Knowledge, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Layton, E. (1971) The Revolt of the Engineers: Social Responsibility and the American Engineering Profession, Press of the Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Opragen Publications 1999

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Science and Technology StudiesUniversity College LondonLondonUnited Kingdom

Personalised recommendations