Skip to main content
Log in

Imaginative Value Sensitive Design: Using Moral Imagination Theory to Inform Responsible Technology Design

  • Original Research/Scholarship
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Safe-by-design (SBD) frameworks for the development of emerging technologies have become an ever more popular means by which scholars argue that transformative emerging technologies can safely incorporate human values. One such popular SBD methodology is called value sensitive design (VSD). A central tenet of this design methodology is to investigate stakeholder values and design those values into technologies during early stage research and development. To accomplish this, the VSD framework mandates that designers consult the philosophical and ethical literature to best determine how to weigh moral trade-offs. However, the VSD framework also concedes the universalism of moral values, particularly the values of freedom, autonomy, equality trust and privacy justice. This paper argues that the VSD methodology, particularly applied to nano-bio-info-cogno technologies, has an insufficient grounding for the determination of moral values. As such, an exploration of the value-investigations of VSD are deconstructed to illustrate both its strengths and weaknesses. This paper also provides possible modalities for the strengthening of the VSD methodology, particularly through the application of moral imagination and how moral imagination exceeds the boundaries of moral intuitions in the development of novel technologies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The recent literature in technology studies has argued for the inseparability and against the bifurcation of the nature/culture dichotomy, and similarly against the privileging of human values over the values of nonhuman animals (see for example Harman 2018; Morton 2016).

  2. Universalism is not equivocal with absolutism. The former argues that moral values are independent of socio-cultural differences, whereas the latter is concerned with intrinsically right/wrong actions.

  3. Here ‘absolute’ refers to ‘moral absolutism’ in which there is an objective basis on which ethical beliefs can be evaluated.

  4. See also Critique of Practical Reason where Immanuel Kant states along these lines that; “Inclination is blind and servile, whether it is kindly or not; and when morality is in question, reason must not play the part of mere guardian to inclination but, disregarding it altogether, must attend solely to its own interest as pure practical reason” (Kant 2015, 5:118; see also KpV 5:71–72).

  5. Transformative being the operative term here; it’s particularly within a narrative and linguistic evaluation where substantial change occurs.

  6. Correlationism was first coined by Quentin Meillassoux (2008) to describe the post-Kantian anthropocentric conceit that “we only ever have access to the correlation between thinking and being, and never to either term considered apart from the other” (Meillassoux 2009, 5). This idea has been a common ground for criticism that has united the speculative realist philosophers.

  7. I have elsewhere criticised this Western moral dominance towards a preliminary course of adopting an approach of intersubjectivity (Umbrello 2018).

References

  • Baum, S. D. (2016). On the promotion of safe and socially beneficial artificial intelligence. AI and Society. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-016-0677-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borges, M. (2004). What can Kant teach us about emotions? The Journal of Philosophy,101(3), 140–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borning, A., & Muller, M. (2012). Next steps for value sensitive design. In Proceedings of the 2012 ACM annual conference on human factors in computing systemsCHI’12 (p. 1125). https://doi.org/10.1145/2207676.2208560.

  • Brey, P. A. E. (2010). Philosophy of technology after the empirical turn. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology,14(1), 36–48. https://doi.org/10.5840/techne20101416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brey, P. A. E. (2012). Values in technology and disclosive computer ethics. In L. Floridi (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of information and computer ethics (pp. 41–58). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511845239.004.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, P., & Thomas, L. (2015). An inclusive, value sensitive design perspective on future identity technologies. ACM Transactions on Computer-Human Interaction,22(5), 1–28. https://doi.org/10.1145/2778972.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caviola, L., Mannino, A., Savulescu, J., & Faulmuller, N. (2014). Cognitive biases can affect moral intuitions about cognitive enhancement. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience,8, 1–5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2014.00195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contissa, G., Lagioia, F., & Sartor, G. (2017). The ethical knob: Ethically-customisable automated vehicles and the law. Artificial Intelligence and Law,25(3), 365–378. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-017-9211-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correljé, A., Cuppen, E., Dignum, M., Pesch, U., & Taebi, B. (2015). Responsible innovation in energy projects: Values in the design of technologies, Institutions and Stakeholder Interactions 1 (Draft Version for Forthcoming Book). In B.-J. Koops, I. Oosterlaken, H. Romijn, T. Swierstra, & J. van den Hoven (Eds.), Responsible innovation (Vol. 2, pp. 183–200). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J., & Nathan, L. P. (2015). Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design: Sources, theory, values and application domains. In J. van den Hoven, P. E. Vermaas & I. van de Poel (Eds.), Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design: Sources, theory, values and application domains (pp. 12–40). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6970-0.

  • De Tiège, A., Van de Peer, Y., Braeckman, J., & Tanghe, K. B. (2018). The sociobiology of genes: The gene’s eye view as a unifying behavioural-ecological framework for biological evolution. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,40(1), 6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dechesne, F., Warnier, M., & van den Hoven, J. (2013). Ethical requirements for reconfigurable sensor technology: A challenge for value sensitive design. Ethics and Information Technology,15(3), 173–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-013-9326-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denning, T., Kohno, T., & Levy, H. M. (2013). A framework for evaluating security risks associated with technologies used at home. Communications of the ACM. https://doi.org/10.1145/2398356.2398377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ervas, F., Gola, E., & Rossi, M. G. (2018). Argumentation as a bridge between metaphor and reasoning. In S. Oswald, T. Herman & J. Jacquin (Eds.), Argumentation and language—Linguistic, cognitive and discursive explorations (pp. 153–170). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A., & Etzioni, O. (2016). AI assisted ethics. Ethics and Information Technology,18(2), 149–156. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-016-9400-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier, G., & Turner, M. (2008a). Rethinking metaphor. In R. W. Gibbs (Ed.), Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1290862.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier, G., & Turner, M. B. (2008b). Conceptual projection and middle spaces. SSRN Electronic Journal. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1290862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fesmire, S. (2003). John Dewey and moral imagination: Pragmatism in ethics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, M., Howe, D. C., & Nissenbaum, H. (2008). Embodying values in technology: Theory and practice. In J. van den Hoven & J. Weckert (Eds.), Information technology and moral philosophy (pp. 322–353). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B. (1996). Value-sensitive design. Interactions,3(6), 16–23. https://doi.org/10.1145/242485.242493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B. (1997). Human values and the design of computer technology. In B. Friedman (Ed.) CSLI Publications. https://web.stanford.edu/group/cslipublications/cslipublications/site/1575860805.shtml#.

  • Friedman, B., Hendry, D. G., & Borning, A. (2017). A survey of value sensitive design methods. Foundations and Trends in Human-Computer Interaction,11(2), 63–125. https://doi.org/10.1561/1100000015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., & Kahn, P. H., Jr. (2003a). Human values, ethics, and design. In J. A. Jacko & A. Sears (Eds.), The human-computer interaction handbook (pp. 1177–1201). Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., & Kahn, P. H., Jr. (2003b). Human values, ethics, and design. In The human-computer interaction handbook (pp. 1177–1201). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Mahwah, NJ.

  • Friedman, B., Kahn, P. H., Jr., & Borning, A. (2006). Value sensitive design and information systems (PREPRINT). Human-Computer Interaction and Management Information Systems: Foundations. https://doi.org/10.1145/242485.242493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., Kahn, P. H., Jr., & Borinng, A. (2008). Value sensitive design and information systems. In K. E. Himma & H. T. Tavani (Eds.), The Handbook of information and computer ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., Kahn, P. H., Jr., Borning, A., & Huldtgren, A. (2013). Value sensitive design and information systems. In N. Doorn, D. Schuurbiers, I. van de Poel, & M. E. Gorman (Eds.), Early engagement and new technologies: Opening up the Laboratory (pp. 55–95). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7844-3_4.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W., Jr. (2006). Embodiment and cognitive science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W., Jr. (2017). Metaphor wars. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gogoll, J., & Müller, J. F. (2017). Autonomous cars: In favor of a mandatory ethics setting. Science and Engineering Ethics,23(3), 681–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, B. (2016). Mechanism and meaning. In J. Hyman (Ed.), Investigating psychology (pp. 62–80). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. The Innate Mind,3, 367–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. J. (2016). Staying with the trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (2016). Immaterialism: Objects and social theory. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (2018a). Object-oriented ontology: A new theory of everything. New York, NY: Penguin Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (2018b). Object-oriented ontology. Pelican.

  • Harmon, J. L. (2016). The normative architecture of reality: Towards an object-oriented ethics. Lexington: University of Kentucky. https://doi.org/10.13023/etd.2016.114.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, J. (2014). Compassionate AI and selfless robots: A buddhist approach. In P. Lin, K. Abney, & G. A. Bekey (Eds.), Robot ethics: The ethical and social implications of robotics (pp. 69–84). Boston: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huldtgren, A. (2014). Design for values in ICT. In J. van den Hoven, P. E. Vermaas, & I. van de Poel (Eds.), Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design: Sources, theory, values and application domains (pp. 1–24). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6994-6_35-1.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1993). Moral imagination: Implications of cognitive science for ethics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2013). The body in the mind: The bodily basis of meaning, imagination, and reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2014). Morality for humans: Ethical understanding from the perspective of cognitive science. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, C. H. (1987). Plato’s theory of desire. The Review of Metaphysics,41(1), 77–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2015). Critical neutralization of the antinomy of practical reason. In A. Reath & M. Gregor (Eds.), The critique of practical reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemeny, M. E. (2009). Psychobiological responses to social threat: Evolution of a psychological model in psychoneuroimmunology. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krakowiak, K. M., & Tsay-Vogel, M. (2015). The dual role of morally ambiguous characters: Examining the effect of morality salience on narrative responses. Human Communication Research,41(3), 390–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramp, M. K. (2003). Exploring life and experience through narrative inquiry. In O. Lagerspetz, J. Antfolk, Y. Gustafsson, & C. Kronqvist (Eds.), Foundations for research (pp. 119–138). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (2003). Metaphors we live by. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2017). Facing Gaia: Eight lectures on the new climatic regime. Polity.

  • Le Dantec, C. A., Poole, E. S., & Wyche, S. P. (2009). Values as lived experience: Evolving value sensitive design in support of value discovery. In Proceedings of the SIGCHI conference on human factors in computing systems. CHI’09 (pp. 1141–1150). New York, NY, USA: ACM. https://doi.org/10.1145/1518701.1518875.

  • Meillassoux, Q. (2008). In R. Brassier (Ed.), After finitude: An essay on the necessity of contingency. Bloomsbury Publishing.

  • Meillassoux, Q. (2009). In R. Brassier (Ed.), After finitude: An essay on the necessity of contingency. Bloomsbury Publishing. https://www.bloomsbury.com/uk/after-finitude-9781441173836.

  • Mordini, E. (2007). The narrative dimension of nanotechnology. Nanotechnology Perceptions,3, 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton, T. (2016). Dark ecology: For a logic of future coexistence. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, T. (2018). Being ecological. Boston, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, V. C., & Bostrom, N. (2016). Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion BT. In V. C. Müller (Ed.), Fundamental issues of artificial intelligence (pp. 555–572). Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26485-1_33.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. F., Gregor, P., Morgan, M., Pullin, G., & Macaulay, C. (2011). User-sensitive inclusive design. Universal Access in the Information Society,10(3), 235–243. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10209-010-0203-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in greek tragedy and philosophy (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, J. B. (1999). Maps of meaning: The architecture of belief. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinch, T., & Bijker, W. E. (1987). The social construction of facts and artifacts. In W. E. Bijker, T. P. Hughes, & T. Pinch (Eds.), The social construction of technological systems: New directions in the sociology and history of technology. Boston: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history (Vol. 3). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roache, R. (2008). Ethics, speculation, and values. NanoEthics,2(3), 317–327. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-008-0050-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolf, M., & Crook, N. (2016). What if: Robots create novel goals? Ethics based on social value systems. In CEUR workshop proceedings (pp. 20–25).

  • Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarbin, T. R. (2001). Embodiment and the narrative structure of emotional life. Narrative Inquiry,11(1), 217–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segerstrale, U. (2016). The westermarck thesis as a thinking tool for sociobiology. In R. Pfau, M. Steinbach & B. Woll (Eds.), Evolution, human behaviour and morality (pp. 97–118). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1976). The schizophrenia of modern ethical theories. Journal of Philosophy,73(14), 453–466. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taub, S. (2012). Iconicity and metaphor. In Sign languageAn international handbook (pp. 388–412). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

  • Tilmouth, C. (2007). Passion’s triumph over reason: A history of the moral imagination from spenser to rochester. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timmermans, J., Zhao, Y., & van den Hoven, J. (2011). Ethics and nanopharmacy: Value sensitive design of new drugs. NanoEthics,5(3), 269–283. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-011-0135-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, M. (1994). Reading minds: The study of English in the age of cognitive science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, M. (2006). The artful mind: Cognitive science and the riddle of human creativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, M. (2010). Conceptual integration. In D. Geeraerts & H. Cuyckens (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of cognitive linguistics. Oxford Handbooks Online. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199738632.013.0015.

  • Turner, M., & Fauconnier, G. (2000). Metaphor, metonymy, and binding. In A. Barcelona (Ed.), Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cognitive perspective (Vol. 356). Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umbrello, S. (2018). The moral psychology of value sensitive design: The methodological issues of moral intuitions for responsible innovation. Journal of Responsible Innovation,5(2), 186–200. https://doi.org/10.1080/23299460.2018.1457401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umbrello, S. (2019a). Atomically precise manufacturing and responsible innovation: A value sensitive design approach to explorative nanophilosophy. International Journal of Technoethics,10(2), 10. https://doi.org/10.2139/srn.3141478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umbrello, S. (2019b). Beneficial artificial intelligence coordination by means of a value sensitive design approach. Big Data and Cognitive Computing,3(1), 5. https://doi.org/10.3390/bdcc3010005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umbrello, S., & Baum, S. D. (2018). Evaluating future nanotechnology: The net societal impacts of atomically precise manufacturing. Futures,100, 63–73. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2018.04.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umbrello, S., & De Bellis, A. F. (2018). A value-sensitive design approach to intelligent agents. In R. V. Yampolskiy (Ed.), Artificial intelligence safety and security (pp. 395–410). Boca Raton: CRC Press. https://doi.org/10.13140/rg.2.2.17162.77762.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, R. M. (1976). Knowledge and politics. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J. (2013). Architecture and value-sensitive design. In C. Basta & S. Moroni (Eds.), Ethics, design and planning of the built environment (Vol. 224). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J. (2017). The design turn in applied ethics. In J. van den Hoven, S. Miller, & T. Pogge (Eds.), Designing in ethics (pp. 11–31). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9780511844317.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J., Lokhorst, G. J., & van de Poel, I. (2012). Engineering and the problem of moral overload. Science and Engineering Ethics,18(1), 143–155. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9277-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J., & Manders-Huits, N. (2009). Value-sensitive design. In J. K. B. Olsen, S. A. Pedersen, & V. F. Hendricks (Eds.), In a companion to the philosophy of technology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781444310795.ch86.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J., & Weckert, J. (Eds.). (2008). Information technology and moral philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Wynsberghe, A. (2012). Designing robots with care: Creating an ethical framework for the future design and implementation of care robots. Enschede: University of Twente. https://doi.org/10.3990/1.9789036533911.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Wynsberghe, A. (2013). A method for integrating ethics into the design of robots. Industrial Robot: An International Journal,40(5), 433–440. https://doi.org/10.1108/IR-12-2012-451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Wynsberghe, A. (2016). Service robots, care ethics, and design. Ethics and Information Technology,18(4), 311–321. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-016-9409-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Wynsberghe, A., & Robbins, S. (2014). Ethicist as designer: A pragmatic approach to ethics in the lab. Science and Engineering Ethics,20(4), 947–961. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-013-9498-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (2017). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Warnier, M., Dechesne, F., & Brazier, F. (2014). Design for the value of privacy. In J. van den Hoven, P. E. Vermaas, & I. van de Poel (Eds.), Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design: Sources, theory, values and application domains (pp. 1–14). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6994-6_17-1.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (1999). Kant’s ethical thought. Modern European Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9781139173254.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper has been adapted from a dissertation accepted and published by the University of Edinburgh. I would like to thank the two anonymous reviews that provided both encouraging and constructive comments on this manuscript. Any remaining errors are the author’s alone. The view expressed in this paper do not necessarily reflect those of the Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Umbrello.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Umbrello, S. Imaginative Value Sensitive Design: Using Moral Imagination Theory to Inform Responsible Technology Design. Sci Eng Ethics 26, 575–595 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-019-00104-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-019-00104-4

Keywords

Navigation