Skip to main content
Log in

Virtue and the Scientist: Using Virtue Ethics to Examine Science’s Ethical and Moral Challenges

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

As science has grown in size and scope, it has also presented a number of ethical and moral challenges. Approaching these challenges from an ethical framework can provide guidance when engaging with them. In this article, I place science within a virtue ethics framework, as discussed by Aristotle. By framing science within virtue ethics, I discuss what virtue ethics entails for the practicing scientist. Virtue ethics holds that each person should work towards her conception of flourishing where the virtues enable her to realize that conception. The virtues must become part of the scientist’s character, undergirding her intentions and motivations, as well as the resulting decisions and actions. The virtue of phronêsis, or practical wisdom, is critical for cultivating virtue, enabling the moral agent to discern the appropriate actions for a particular situation. In exercising phronêsis, the scientist considers the situation from multiple perspectives for an in-depth and nuanced understanding of the situation, discerns the relevant factors, and settles upon an appropriate decision. I examine goods internal to a practice, which are constitutive of science practiced well and discuss the role of phronêsis when grappling with science’s ethical and moral features and how the scientist might exercise it. Although phronêsis is important for producing scientific knowledge, it is equally critical for working through the moral and ethical questions science poses.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics may be widely discussed ethical frameworks amongst philosophers, most people are familiar with their general features, even if they are not familiar with them as philosophical constructs, as these frameworks all figure into how people make ethical decisions.

  2. For additional reading about this, see Toulmin (1990).

  3. It is important to note that each ethical system has its blind spots and none can satisfactorily address all the moral issues in a complex situation and each draws attention to different features. Instead, virtue ethics, along with Kantianism and utilitarianism and other frameworks not discussed, should be used alongside each other to supplement their respective shortcomings.

  4. Subsequent references to the Nicomachean Ethics will come from the Irwin translation, using Bekker numbers to point the reader to the passage.

  5. It should be pointed out that this is a simplified discussion of science. Much of scientists’ work is collaborative and interdisciplinary, where no one person decides the form and content of the experiments, their interpretation, and so forth. However, even within group collaborations, individual scientists must exercise phronêsis in creating and interpreting knowledge for their part of the collaboration, as well as figuring out how best to interact with their collaborators.

  6. While I focus more on the internal goods than the external ones, I do not mean to be dismissive of them. Although the external goods are not the reasons the virtuous practitioner does the practice, they are still critical to the sustainment and continuation of the practice. For example, accumulating a certain amount of wealth is necessary because it enables the practitioner to focus on the achieving the practice’s internal goods. Indeed many practices are sustained by the institutions that house them, where a main focus of these institutions is achieving the external goods necessary for the practice’s continued existence. Similarly, the useful technologies developed from scientific knowledge are external goods (as science can produce reliable knowledge about the natural world without yielding any useful technologies), which are highly prized and often contribute to the furthering of science’s internal goods in a particular area, through increasing financial and social support.

  7. To be an excellent practitioner is not only excellence in meeting the practice’s internal goods, e.g. excellence in producing knowledge about the natural world. It is also to uphold the internal goods as worthy ends in and of themselves and not as means for external goods. While the excellent practitioner may in part be motivated by external goods, she is not solely motivated by them.

  8. This example is based on research efforts that manipulate various strains of the flu virus to better understand the pandemic threats posed. Most recently this type of work was advocated by Fouchier and Kawaoka, on behalf of twenty other authors, who propose to manipulate the H7N9 subtype of avian influenza A that may result in change of function, including drug resistance, pathogenicity, transmissibility, adaptability, and immunogenicity (Fouchier and Kawaoka 2013).

  9. Presently, there are little to no definitive guidelines regarding the dissemination of knowledge that could directly lead to the misuse of that knowledge. Such studies involving “dual-use research of concern” are assessed by the National Science Advisory Board for Biosecurity, which, in 2012, recommended the redaction of papers examining the transmissibility of the avian influenza virus H5N1, out of concern for its misuse. The papers were redacted, contingent upon the creation of a mechanism that gave appropriate researchers and officials access to the complete information. Recommendations for additional assessment and oversight of dual-use research in general have been made (Faden and Karron 2012; Gostin 2012; Osterholm and Relman 2012).

  10. Depending upon the institution’s policies, the decision to euthanize the mice ahead of schedule may require involvement of the IACUC or institution’s veterinarian. However, institutions may also have policies that permit the researchers to immediately euthanize animals for humane reasons.

References

  • Ackrill, J. L. (1980). Aristotle on eudaimonia. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s ethics (pp. 15–33). Los Angeles, CA: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford: Oxford University.

  • Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

  • Berns, K. I., Casadevall, A., Cohen, M. L., Ehrlich, S. A., Enquist, L. W., Fitch, J. P., et al. (2012). Adaptations of avian flu virus are a cause for concern. Science, 335(6069), 660–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, J. M. (1975). Reason and human good in Aristotle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, J. (1996). Partiality and the virtues. In R. Crisp (Ed.), How should one live? Essays on the virtues (pp. 59–76). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford-Brown, D. J. (1997). Virtue as the basis of engineering ethics. Science and Engineering Ethics, 3(4), 481–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, N. O. (1984). Practical reason, Aristotle, and weakness of the will. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faden, R. R., & Karron, R. A. (2012). The obligation to prevent the next dual-use controversy. Science, 335(6070), 802–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fouchier, R. A. M., & Kawaoka, Y. (2013). Gain-of-function experiments on H7N9. Nature, 500(7461), 150–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gostin, L. O. (2012). The influenza controversy: Should limits be placed on science? Hastings Center Report, 42(3), 12–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, P. (1994). Aristotle on dividing the soul and uniting the virtues. Phronesis, 39(3), 275–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, C. E. (2008). The good engineer: Giving virtue its due in engineering ethics. Science and Engineering Ethics, 14(2), 153–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2001). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kent, B. (1999). Moral growth and the unity of the virtues. In D. Carr & J. W. Steutel (Eds.), Virtue ethics and moral education (pp. 113–128). Florence, KY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2007). After virtue: A study in moral theory (3rd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malakoff, D. (2013). Critics skeptical as flu scientists argue for controversial H7N9 studies. Science, 341(6146), 601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Institute of Health & Alcohol Drug Abuse and Mental Health Administration. (1989). Requirement for programs on the responsible conduct of research in national research service award institutional training programs. In: National institutes of health guide for grants and contracts. (Vol. 18, pp. 1–13). Bethesda, MD: National Institutes of Health.

  • Noel, J. (1999). On the varieties of Phronesis. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 31(3), 273–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1986). The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyberg, D. (2008). The morality of everyday activities: Not the right, but the good thing to do. Journal of Business Ethics, 81(3), 587–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakley, J. (1996). Varieties of virtue ethics. Ratio, 9(2), 128–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osterholm, M. T., & Relman, D. A. (2012). Creating a mammalian-transmissible A/H5N1 influenza virus: Social contracts, prudence, and alternative perspectives. The Journal of Infectious Diseases, 205(11), 1636–1638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E. D. (1995). Toward a virtue-based normative ethics for the health professions. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 5(3), 253–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E. D. (2002). Professionalism, profession and the virtues of the good physician. Mount Sinai Journal of Medicine, 69(6), 378–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E. D. (2007). Professing medicine, virtue based ethics, and the retrieval of professionalism. In R. L. Walker & P. J. Ivanhoe (Eds.), Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems (pp. 61–85). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E. D., & Thomasma, D. C. (1993). The virtues in medical practice. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiser, S. J., & Bulger, R. E. (1997). The social responsibilities of biological scientists. Science and Engineering Ethics, 3(2), 137–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Relman, D. A. (2013). The increasingly compelling moral responsibilities of life scientists. Hastings Center Report, 43(2), 34–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. C. (2012). Practical intelligence and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schön, D. A. (1983). The reflective practitioner: How professionals think in action. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shields, C. (2008). Aristotle. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle. Accessed October 16, 2013.

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1994). Ethics of scientific research. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steneck, N. H., & Bulger, R. E. (2007). The history, purpose, and future of instruction in the responsible conduct of research. Academic Medicine, 82(9), 829–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1996). Emotions reveal value and help cure the schizophrenia of modern ethical theories. In R. Crisp (Ed.), How should one live? Essays on the virtues (pp. 171–190). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stovall, P. (2011). Professional virtue and professional self-awareness: A case study in engineering ethics. Science and Engineering Ethics, 17(1), 109–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasma, D. (2002). Aristotle, phronesis, and postmodern bioethics. In M. G. Kuczewski & R. Polansky (Eds.), Bioethics: Ancient themes in contemporary issues (pp. 67–92). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R. L., & Ivanhoe, P. J. (Eds.). (2007). Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Howard Brody and W. Austin Elam for their thoughtful comments on previous drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jiin-Yu Chen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Chen, JY. Virtue and the Scientist: Using Virtue Ethics to Examine Science’s Ethical and Moral Challenges. Sci Eng Ethics 21, 75–94 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-014-9522-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-014-9522-3

Keywords

Navigation