Science and Engineering Ethics

, Volume 20, Issue 2, pp 329–343 | Cite as

When Technologies Makes Good People Do Bad Things: Another Argument Against the Value-Neutrality of Technologies

Original Paper

Abstract

Although many scientists and engineers insist that technologies are value-neutral, philosophers of technology have long argued that they are wrong. In this paper, I introduce a new argument against the claim that technologies are value-neutral. This argument complements and extends, rather than replaces, existing arguments against value-neutrality. I formulate the Value-Neutrality Thesis, roughly, as the claim that a technological innovation can have bad effects, on balance, only if its users have “vicious” or condemnable preferences. After sketching a microeconomic model for explaining or predicting a technology’s impact on individuals’ behavior, I argue that a particular technological innovation can create or exacerbate collective action problems, even in the absence of vicious preferences. Technologies do this by increasing the net utility of refusing to cooperate. I also argue that a particular technological innovation can induce short-sighted behavior because of humans’ tendency to discount future benefits too steeply. I suggest some possible extensions of my microeconomic model of technological impacts. These extensions would enable philosophers of technology to consider agents with mixed motives—i.e., agents who harbor some vicious preferences but also some aversion to acting on them—and to apply the model to questions about the professional responsibilities of engineers, scientists, and other inventors.

Keywords

Value-neutrality Technology ethics Instrumentalism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Chris Alen Sula and two anonymous referees for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

References

  1. Brey, P. (2010). Philosophy of technology after the empirical turn. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology, 14(1), 36–48.Google Scholar
  2. Green, L., & Myerson, J. (2004). A discounting framework for choice with delayed and probabilistic rewards. Psychological Bulletin, 130(5), 769–792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1243–1248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Held, V. (2006). The ethics of care: Personal, political, and global. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Illies, C., & Meijers, A. (2009). Artefacts without agency. The Monist, 92(3), 420–440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Kamm, F. M. (2006). Intricate ethics: Rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Koepsell, D. (2010). On genies and bottles: Scientists’ moral responsibility and dangerous technology R&D. Science and Engineering Ethics, 16(1), 119–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  9. Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Putnam, R. (2000). Bowling alone: The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
  11. Radder, H. (2009). Why technologies are inherently normative. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Handbook of the philosophy of science, vol. 9: Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences (pp. 887–921). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Railton, P. (1984). Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13(2), 134–171.Google Scholar
  13. Van de Poel, I. (2001). Investigating ethical issues in engineering design. Science and Engineering Ethics, 7(3), 429–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Williams, B. (1973). A critique of utilitarianism. In J. J. C. Smart & B. Williams (Eds.), Utilitarianism: For and against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Winner, L. (1986). The whale and the reactor: A search for limits in an age of high technology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of Alabama at BirminghamBirminghamUSA

Personalised recommendations