Skip to main content
Log in

Specialization, implicit coordination and organizational performance: trading off common and idiosyncratic knowledge

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Review of Managerial Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper reconsiders the trade-off between specialization and coordination by focusing on as yet neglected forms of implicit coordination. While specialization draws on idiosyncratic knowledge pertaining to the worker’s specific tasks and environment, implicit coordination is based on knowledge common to all workers. Accordingly, the trade-off between specialization and coordination translates into one between idiosyncratic and common knowledge. Investigating this trade-off I determine the organization’s optimal knowledge structure depending on a number of organizational and environmental parameters. Further extensions of the model allow for explicit coordination through communication, differentiate between common knowledge at the corporate level and departmental level, and apply important results to the issue of corporate culture, interpreted as a specific form of common knowledge that likewise facilitates implicit coordination.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The basic intuition of a fundamental trade-off between specialization and coordination certainly extends back to before Becker and Murphy (1992). A classical reference, for instance, is March and Simon (1958). However, the paper by Becker and Murphy is generally considered the starting point of economic analysis of this trade-off.

  2. Although Hume ( 1976 ) already made explicit reference to the role of common knowledge in the coordination of human activities, it was Schelling (1960) who provided seminal ideas and Lewis (1969) who first gave a systematic account of common knowledge and its coordinative impact. The concept of common knowledge has subsequently been addressed in several attempts at rigorous formalization, e.g., by Aumann (1976), Milgrom (1981), and Barwise (1988).

  3. This does of course not preclude vertical and lateral communication previous to a specific coordination problem as an important means for the inception of common knowledge. In fact, communication manifested in general instructions, manuals and brochures, trainings and social events, staff newsletters and small talk, etc. is an important channel for synchronizing individual knowledge sets and providing staff with common background knowledge. The distinguishing mark of implicit coordination, however, is that it aligns decentralized actions or decisions without communication when faced with a specific coordination problem.

  4. More precisely, specialization in terms of narrowing the range of tasks a particular individual has to perform may actually entail two effects with respect to the individual’s knowledge set: On the one hand the set is itself narrowed, as it covers fewer tasks; on the other hand it is deepened, as concentration on fewer tasks more thoroughly exploits learning curve effects. Although these effects are in a sense opposites in their implications for workers’ requirements for task-specific human capital, they unambiguously attenuate workers’ wherewithal for implicit coordination and therefore underpin the model’s focal trade-off.

  5. In this example the order form itself certainly represents an act of communication informing the production department about the promised delivery date. But this is unproblematic as the proposed model does not exclude communication whatsoever. Decisive is that the coordination itself, i.e. the selection of a new coordination equilibrium, was brought about without any communication in the face of the specific situation but solely on the basis of common knowledge.

  6. For a more detailed discussion of φ(·), see Sect. 6. For a generalization accounting for an arbitrary φ(·), refer to Appendix 1. Alternatively, even if less fitting to the underlying story, implicit coordination could also have been modeled as the observation of a noisy signal with the noise rate being a positive function of p. The basic results, however, would remain unaffected.

  7. I show in this extended setting that coordination by common knowledge is (partially) crowded out by another form of coordination, namely by a sticking to the status quo and reduced adaptation similar to that ascertained by Dessein and Santos (2006). Nevertheless, the main propositions hold true.

  8. In light of numerous empirical studies finding a positive correlation between organization size and degree of internal specialization (Donaldson 1986 and Miller 1987 provide comprehensive surveys), this result seems at the same time surprising and needs further qualification. It hinges on specific assumptions that are only to a certain extent applicable to real-world organizations. On the one hand, it supposes that the extent of complementarity is driven by the overall size of the organization. This relation, however, is not only mediated by the specific production process and technology; organizations command several means of keeping complementarities at bay. In particular, organizational modularization—from simple departmentalization to sophisticated forms such as internal hybrids and loosely coupled organization (e.g., Zenger and Hesterly 1997; Foss 2003)—significantly reduces organization-wide interdependencies. It thus justifies the relaxation of this assumption and accounts for the existence of large scale and internally highly specialized manufacturers. (Sect. 6 presents an extension of the basic model considering departmentalization of the organization.) Furthermore, such organizations rely heavily on alternative mechanisms of coordination, especially authoritative decision-making and fiat, which could provide further explanations for their prosperity in spite of Proposition 3.

  9. This assumption is made to facilitate the further exposition. Although it implies that explicit coordination through communication always performs worse than (or at best equally well in case of τ = 1 as) implicit coordination through common knowledge, this assumption is innocuous. No result derived in the following hinges on it.

  10. For work concerned with an in-depth analysis of this trade-off between specialization and communication see the related literature referenced in Sect. 2.

  11. Let Ω be the set of all possible events and contingencies the organization could face, ordered by the frequency of occurrence such that a corresponding density function f(Z) with Z ∈ Ω is non-increasing. If the subset of events the organization can successfully coordinate is proportional to the fraction of common knowledge, then the corresponding cumulative distribution function F(Z) can be interpreted as φ(p i ), i ∈ {2, 3}, exhibiting the required properties.

  12. Subsuming such a notion of corporate culture under common knowledge seems unproblematic, as the latter is assumed in a broad sense to encompass besides mere propositional knowledge cognitive frames and categories more generally (including values, norms, beliefs, meanings, conventions and principles), as long as these are shared by a group of employees and guide employees’ behavior. Such a broad understanding of common knowledge, however, may preclude a conceptual equation of corporate culture and common knowledge, as the latter can comprise content beyond the conceptual scope of corporate culture (which differs in the work of different authors).

  13. Sorensen initially hypothesized that corporate culture fosters organizational inertia and that therefore “[a]s industry volatility increases, the positive effect of culture strength on mean performance declines” (p. 77), which is quite the opposite to Proposition 2′. His empirical investigation of this relationship, using a sample of large, publicly traded firms in 18 markets, however, did not support his hypothesis and is therefore consistent with Proposition 2′ and the view of corporate culture expressed here.

References

  • Allaire Y, Firsirotu ME (1984) Theories of organizational culture. Organ Stud 5(3):193–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angeletos GM, Pavan A (2004) Transparency of information and coordination in economies with investment complementarities. Am Econ Rev 94:91–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angeletos GM, Pavan A (2007a) Efficient use of information and social value of information. Econometrica 75:1103–1142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angeletos GM, Pavan A (2007b) Socially optimal coordination: characterization and policy implications. J Eur Econ Assoc 5:585–593

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (1986) Horizontal vs. vertical information structure of the firm. Am Econ Rev 76:971–983

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1962) The economic implications of learning by doing. Rev Econ Stud 29:155–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1974) The limits of organization. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1985) Informational structure of the firm. Am Econ Rev 75:303–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann RJ (1976) Agreeing to disagree. Ann Stat 4:1236–1239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin CY, Clark KB (2000) Design rules vol. 1: the power of modularity. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise J (1988) Three views of common knowledge. In: Yardi YM (ed) Proceedings of the 2nd conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge. Morgan Kaufman, San Francisco, pp 365–379

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS, Murphy KM (1992) The division of labor, coordination costs, and knowledge. Q J Econ 107:1137–1160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boisnier A, Chatman JA (2003) The role of subcultures in agile organizations. In: Peterson R, Mannix E (eds) Leading and managing people in dynamic organizations. Earlbaum, Mahwah, pp 87–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton P, Dewatripont M (1994) The firm as a communication network. Q J Econ 109:809–839

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnahan TF, Brynjolfsson E, Hitt LM (2002) Information technology, workplace organization, and the demand for skilled labor: firm-level evidence. Q J Econ 117:339–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brynjolfsson E, Hitt LM (2000) Beyond computation: information technology, organizational transformation and business performance. J Econ Perspect 14:23–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cable DM, Aiman-Smith L, Edwards JR (2000) The sources and accuracy of job applicants’ beliefs about organizational culture. Acad Manag J 43(6):1076–1085

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer C, Knez M (1996) Coordination, organizational boundaries and fads in business practices. Ind Corp Change 5:89–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatman JA (1991) Matching people and organizations: selection and socialization in public accounting firms. Admin Sci Q 36:459–484

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crémer J (1990) Common knowledge and the co-ordination of economic activities. In: Aoki M, Gustafsson B, Williamson OE (eds) The firm as a nexus of treaties. Sage, London, pp 53–76

    Google Scholar 

  • Crémer J (1993) Corporate culture and shared knowledge. Ind Corp Change 2:351–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crémer J, Garicano L, Prat A (2007) Language and the theory of the firm. Q J Econ 122:373–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz H (1991) The theory of the firm revisited. In: Williamson OE, Winter SG (eds) The nature of the firm: origins, evolution, and development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 159–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Denison DR (1990) Corporate culture and organizational effectiveness. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dessein W, Santos T (2006) Adaptive organizations. J Polit Econ 114:956–995

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson L (1986) Size and bureaucracy in east and west: a preliminary meta analysis. In: Clegg SR, Dunphy DC, Redding SG (eds) The enterprise and management in East Asia. University of Hong Kong Press, Hong Kong, pp 67–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Foss NJ (2003) Selective intervention and internal hybrids: interpreting and learning from the rise and decline of the Oticon spaghetti organization. Organ Sci 14:331–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garicano L (2000) Hierarchies and the organization of knowledge in production. J Polit Econ 108:874–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garicano LE, Rossi-Hansberg E (2006) Organization and inequality in a knowledge economy. Q J Econ 121:1383–1435

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz C (1973) The interpretation of cultures. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons R (2005) Four formal(izable) theories of the firm? J Econ Behav Organ 58:200–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons R, Waldman M (2004) Task-specific human capital. Am Econ Rev 94:203–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginevicius R, Vaitkunaite V (2006) Analysis of organizational culture dimension impacting performance. J Bus Econ Manag 7(4):201–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenan N, Guellec D (1998) Firm organization, technology and performance: an empirical study. Econ Innov New Tech 6:313–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory KL (1983) Native-view paradigms: multiple cultures and culture conflicts in organizations. Admin Sci Q 28:359–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart O, Moore J (2005) On the design of hierarchies: coordination versus specialization. J Polit Econ 113:675–702

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hermalin BE (2001) Economics and corporate culture. In: Cooper CL, Cartwright S, Earley PC (eds) Organizational culture and climate. Wiley, Chichester, pp 217–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstede G (1998) Identifying organizational subcultures: an empirical approach. J Manag Stud 35:1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmström B, Roberts J (1998) The boundaries of the firm revisited. J Econ Perspect 12:73–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoogervorst J, van der Flier H, Koopman P (2004) Implict communcation in organisations: the impact of culture, structure and management practices on employee behaiour. J Manag Psychol 19(3):288–311

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1976) A treatise of human nature. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerimer JM, Slocum JW, Fry LW, Gaines J (1991) Organizational subcultures in a soft bureaucracy: resistance behind the myth and dacade of an official culture. Organ Sci 2:170–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kogut B, Zander U (1996) What firms do? Coordination, identity, and learning. Organ Sci 7:502–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotter JP, Heskett JL (1992) Corporate culture and performance. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps DM (1990) Corporate culture and economic theory. In: Alt JE, Shepsle KA (eds) Perspectives on positive political economy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 90–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Conventions: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck A, Snower DJ (2000) Multitask learning and the reorganization of work: from tayloristic to holistic organization. J Lab Econ 18:353–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck A, Snower DJ (2001) Centralized bargaining and reorganized work: are they compatible? Eur Econ Rev 45:1851–1875

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • March JG, Simon SA (1958) Organizations. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Marschak J, Radner R (1972) Economic theory of teams. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P (1981) An axiomatic characterization of common knowledge. Econometrica 49:219–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P, Roberts J (1992) Economics, organization and management. Prentice-Hall, Upper Saddle River

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller GA (1987) Meta-analysis and the culture-free hypothesis. Organ Stud 8(4):309–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris S, Shin HS (2002) Social value of public information. Am Econ Rev 92:1521–1534

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nooteboom B (2000) Learning and innovation in organizations and economies. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew AM (1979) On studying organizational culture. Admin Sci Q 24:570–581

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prat A (1996) Shared knowledge vs diversified knowledge in teams. J Jpn Int Econ 10:181–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prat A (2002) Should a team be homogeneous? Eur Econ Rev 46:1187–1207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sackmann SA (1992) Culture and subcultures: an analysis of organizational knowledge. Admin Sci Q 37:140–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schein EH (1984) Coming to a new awareness of organization culture. Sloan Manag Rev 25:3–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Schein EH (1992) Organizational culture and leadership. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling TC (1960) The strategy of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Proc Am Phil Soc 106:467–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (2002) Near decomposability and the speed of evolution. Ind Corp Change 11:587–599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1976) The wealth of nations. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen JB (2002) The strength of corporate culture and the reliability of firm performance. Admin Sci Q 47:70–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler GJ (1951) The division of labor is limited by the extent of the market. J Polit Econ 59:185–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Muijen JJ (1998) Organizational culture. In: Drenth PJD, Thierry H, De Wolf CJ (eds) Handbook of work and organizational psychology. Psychology Press, East Sussex, pp 113–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Steen E (2005) On the origin of shared beliefs (and corporate culture). Working Paper 4553-05, Sloan School of Management, MIT

  • Weber RA, Camerer CF (2003) Cultural conflict and merger failure: an experimental approach. Manag Sci 49:400–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenger E (1998) Communities of practice. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wernerfelt B (2004) Organizational languages. J Econ Manag Strategy 13:461–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zenger TR, Hesterly WS (1997) The dissaggregation of corporations: selective intervention, high-powered incentives, and molecular units. Organ Sci 8:209–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Parts of this research were done while the author was visiting INSEAD, Fontainebleau (France). The author is particularly grateful to Bernd Schauenberg and Timothy Van Zandt for numerous discussions and suggestions. The author is also indebted to Todd Bradley, Philipp Jäkel, Ino Vorwerk, numerous seminar participants as well as two anonymous referees for their helpful comments. Financial support from Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Achim Hecker.

Appendices

Appendix 1

In this appendix, I generalize the model as laid out in the main body by showing that the stated propositions also hold for an arbitrary h(p) subject to \( \partial h(p)/\partial p > 0 \), \( \mathop {\lim}\nolimits_{p \to 0} h(p) = 0 \) and \( \mathop {\lim}\nolimits_{p \to 1} h(p) = \infty \) as well as for an arbitrary φ(p) subject to \( \partial \varphi (p)/\partial p < 0 \), φ(0) = 1 and φ(1) = 0. In this case, I derive p* by drawing on the first order condition of the generalized payoff function

$$ E(P(p)) = - n \cdot {\frac{{\alpha + (n - 1) \cdot \beta \cdot (1 - \varphi (p)) \cdot \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \cdot h(p)}}{{{\frac{1}{{\sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}} + h(p)}}}. $$
(22)

p* is then implicitly determined by

$$ 0 = \underbrace {{(n - 1) \cdot \beta \cdot \left({\left({1 - \varphi (p)} \right) \cdot h^{\prime}(p) - \varphi^{\prime}(p) \cdot h(p) - \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \cdot \varphi^{\prime}(p) \cdot h(p)^{2}} \right)}}_{= :A(p)} - \underbrace {{\alpha \cdot h^{\prime}(p)}}_{= :B(p)} $$
(23)

in case of an interior solution, i.e., \( p^{*} \in]0,1[ \), or takes the value \( p^{*} = 1 \) in case of a corner solution. Note that as \( B(0) > A(0) = 0 \), the total absence of specialization (i.e., p = 0) is never optimal. Should there exist multiple local maxima on [0,1], p* clearly takes the value of the global maximum. It can, however, be shown that subject to the additional assumption of the convexity of h(p) as well as of h′(p), multiple maxima can be ruled out.

Generalized Proof of Propositions 13

Assume \( p_{0}^{*} \in]0,1[ \) as the propositions pertain to the case of an interior solution. A decrease of α—an increase of β, \( \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \) , n, respectively—then yields \( A(p_{0}^{*}) > B(p_{0}^{*}) \). We know, however, that B(0) > A(0). From this follows by the intermediate value theorem that \( \exists p_{1}^{*} \in]0,p_{0}^{*} [:A(p_{1}^{*}) = B(p_{1}^{*}) \). \( \square \)

Generalized Proof of Proposition 4

Obtaining the second derivative of (22) with respect to n yields

$$ {\frac{{\partial^{2} E(P)}}{{\partial n^{2}}}} = - {\frac{{2 \cdot \beta \cdot (1 - \varphi (p)) \cdot h(p) \cdot \sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}{{{\frac{1}{{\sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}} + h(p)}}} < 0. $$
(24)

\( \square \)

Generalized Proof of Proposition 5

To incorporate communication I extend (22) by analogy to (12) to

$$ E\left({P(p)} \right) = - n \cdot {\frac{{\alpha + (n - 1) \cdot \beta \cdot (1 - \varphi (p)) \cdot \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \cdot h(p) \cdot \left[{1 - \varphi (p) - (1 - p) \cdot \tau + \varphi (p) \cdot (1 - p) \cdot \tau} \right]}}{{{\frac{1}{{\sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}} + h(p)}}}. $$
(25)

Differentiating this extended payoff function with respect to τ yields

$$ {\frac{\partial E(P)}{\partial \tau}} = {\frac{{n \cdot (n - 1) \cdot \beta \cdot (1 - \varphi (p))^{2} \cdot h(p) \cdot \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \cdot (1 - p)}}{{{\frac{1}{{\sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}} + h(p)}}} \ge 0. $$
(26)

\( \square \)

Generalized Proof of Proposition 6 (constructive sketch)

Assume again the existence of an interior solution, i.e., \( p^{*} \in]0,1[ \). Proposition 6 then implies that \( \exists \bar{\alpha}\forall \tau \in [0,1]:A_{\tau} (p^{*}) = B(p^{*}) \). This \( \bar{\alpha} \) can be obtained as follows: Determine the common intersection point p 0 by choosing two arbitrary \( \tau_{1},\tau_{2} \in [0,1] \), \( \tau_{1} \ne \tau_{2} \), and solving \( A_{{\tau_{1}}} (p) = A_{{\tau_{2}}} (p) \) for p. \( \bar{\alpha} \) is then implicitly determined by \( A_{\tau} (p_{0}) = B(p_{0}) \).\( \square \)

Generalized Proof of Proposition 7

Identical to the one given in the main body of the paper.\( \square \)

Appendix 2

In the basic model I assume that workers seek to maximize the outcome of the actions under their control while they neglect other workers’ results. This induces a kind of goal incongruence that transcends orthodox team theory. In this appendix, I discuss the opposite case of perfect goal alignment (and, concluding, varying degrees of alignment). I will show that in this setting, coordination by common knowledge is (partially) crowded out by another form of coordination, namely by adhering to the status quo and reduced adaptation, similar to that ascertained by Dessein and Santos (2006). Nevertheless, the main propositions hold true.

In case of perfect goal alignment, workers jointly seek to maximize (1). Their decision problem therefore constitutes a game with identical payoffs. In equilibrium, complementary actions are set to \( \forall j \in \{1, \ldots,n\} \backslash \{i\} :b_{ij} = E(a_{i}) \) and primary actions are accordingly chosen to maximize

$$ \tilde{P}\left({a\left| {s_{i},p} \right.} \right) = - \sum\limits_{i = 1}^{n} {\left[{\alpha \cdot \left({E\left({\theta_{i} \left| {s_{i},p} \right.} \right) - a_{i}} \right)^{2} + \left({n - 1} \right) \cdot \beta \cdot \left({1 - \varphi \left(p \right)} \right) \cdot \left({a_{i} - E\left({a_{i}} \right)} \right)^{2}} \right]}, $$
(27)

where \( E(\theta_{i} \left| {s_{i},p} \right.) \) is the ex-post expectation value of θ i after observing signal s i with the precision h(p) as stated by (3). Plugging (3) into (27), I derive the optimal primary action as

$$ \tilde{a}_{i}^{*} = \left({1 - A} \right) \cdot \theta^{0} + A \cdot s_{i},\quad A: = {\frac{\alpha \cdot h(p)}{{\left({\alpha + \left({n - 1} \right) \cdot \beta \cdot \left({1 - \varphi \left(p \right)} \right)} \right) \cdot \left({{\frac{1}{{\sigma_{\theta}^{2}}}} + h(p)} \right)}}} $$
(28)

and the optimal complementary actions accordingly as

$$ \tilde{b}_{ij}^{*} = E(a_{i}) = \theta^{0}. $$
(29)

Whereas the optimal complementary actions remain the same, the worker choosing the primary action underweights her private information (i.e., the signal) as compared to the basic model discussed in the main body. In other words, she consciously forgoes adaptation and therefore local efficiency to foster smooth integration and global coordination of activities. To keep things tractable, I assume again in the following h(p) = p/(1 − p) and φ(p) = 1 − p (a generalization to an arbitrary h(p) and φ(p) would proceed along the lines of Appendix 1). The adjusted payoff function is then given by

$$ \tilde{E}\left({P(p)} \right) = - \frac{1}{p} \cdot \left[{\left({1 - A} \right)^{2} \cdot \alpha \cdot \sigma_{\theta}^{2} \cdot p + A^{2} \cdot \left({\alpha \cdot \left({1 - p} \right) + \left({n - 1} \right) \cdot \beta \cdot p \cdot \left({p \cdot \left({\sigma_{\theta}^{2} - 1} \right) + 1} \right)} \right)} \right], $$
(30)

and the optimal fraction of idiosyncratic knowledge is

$$ \tilde{p}^{*} = \mathop {\arg \max}\limits_{{p \in \left[{0,1} \right]}} \tilde{E}\left({P\left(p \right)} \right) = {\frac{\sqrt \alpha}{{\sqrt {\beta \cdot \left({n - 1} \right) \cdot \left({\sigma_{\theta}^{2} - 1} \right)}}}}. $$
(31)

It is immediate that Propositions 1–3 hold true. Likewise, the validity of Propositions 5 and 7 can easily be shown in this setting. This is not true, however, for Propositions 4 and 6. Additionally, I yield the general result that in case of goal alignment, the optimal fraction of idiosyncratic knowledge is always greater than in the event of goal incongruence, as

$$ \tilde{p}^{*} - p^{*} = {\frac{\sqrt \alpha}{{\sqrt {\beta \cdot \left({n - 1} \right) \cdot \left({\sigma_{\theta}^{2} - 1} \right)}}}} - {\frac{{\sqrt {\beta \cdot \left({n - 1} \right) + \alpha \cdot \left({\sigma_{\theta}^{2} - 1} \right)} - \sqrt {\beta \cdot \left({n - 1} \right)}}}{{\sqrt {\beta \cdot \left({n - 1} \right)} \cdot \left({\sigma_{\theta}^{2} - 1} \right)}}} > 0. $$
(32)

By combining ‘local’ and ‘global’ incentives, i.e., by weighting the opposite cases of goal incongruence (as in the main body) and perfect goal alignment (as in this appendix), one could easily achieve varying degrees of goal alignment. The results then evidently generalize: The higher the degree of goal congruency, the less private information is used for determining primary actions, the more coordination via common knowledge is crowded out by coordination via sticking to the status quo, and the greater is the optimal fraction of idiosyncratic knowledge.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hecker, A. Specialization, implicit coordination and organizational performance: trading off common and idiosyncratic knowledge. Rev Manag Sci 5, 19–47 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11846-010-0043-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11846-010-0043-4

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation