Skip to main content
Log in

(Re)Connecting Analytic Philosophy and Empirical Research: The Example of Ritual Speech Acts and Religious Collectivities

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I demonstrate how philosophical insights and empirical research on the use of religious language can be fruitfully combined to tackle issues regarding the ontology of religious collectivities and the agency of group actors. To do so, I introduce a philosophical framework that draws on speech act theory and recent advances in the fields of collective intentionality and social ontology, with particular attention paid to the work of Raimo Tuomela. Against this backdrop, I discuss a brief case study based on my fieldwork among Jehovah’s Witnesses in Switzerland and Germany. In particular, I call attention to the structure of the Witnesses’ ritual interactions and to the types of speech acts that are performed in their congregational settings. I argue that the communicative framework provided by these rituals is particularly suited to the creation of genuine group intentions that cannot be reduced to the private intentions of the individual group members. In conclusion, I argue that most of the language used in religious contexts does not deviate much from everyday language; however, particular ritual settings can elicit performative effects and constitute new social realities that can have a concrete impact on both individuals and religious groups.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Reasons of space allow me to present only a short summary of my position; an exhaustive discussion will be available in Rota (in preparation). I am thankful to Jens Schlieter and to the three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

  2. The Jehovah’s Witnesses, a chiliastic Christian community, was founded in the 1870s by Charles T. Russell (1852–1916). Today, this growing global denomination has more than eight million active members (see Chryssides, 2016). The empirical data presented here form part of a 3-year SNSF research project (2014–2017) that I co-directed with Oliver Krüger at the University of Fribourg, Switzerland. The data were collected in seventeen long-format semi-structured interviews with Jehovah’s Witnesses in Germany and Switzerland and a quantitative pen-and-pencil survey of four Swiss congregations (N = 183). In line with institutional guidelines and conventional ethical guidelines in the social sciences, all interview excerpts are presented here in anonymized form.

  3. It is worth mentioning that influential philosophers like Michael Bratman also advance conceptually reductivist accounts of collective intentionality as a non-summative network of interlocking personal intentions (see Bratman, 1993, 2014).

  4. In this context, the term ‘linguistic’ extends to ‘non-linguistic communication of the sort which only linguistic practitioners can communicate non-linguistically’ (Schmid, 2012: 359; see also Habermas, 1981).

  5. Margaret Gilbert advances a different philosophical framework with similar consequences for empirical research on collective intentions (e.g., Gilbert, 1989, 1996, 2003). While reasons of space preclude further elaboration of her alternative approach here, I discuss her ideas and their practical application elsewhere (Rota, 2019).

  6. In his work, Tuomela constructs a complex typology of collective intentions, which I cannot discuss here. My focus will be on we-mode collective intentions, which Tuomela describes as ‘full-blown’ collective intentions.

  7. In her work on collective intentions, philosopher Margaret Gilbert comes to a similar conclusion, which she calls the ‘disjunction criterion’ of shared intentionality (see Gilbert, 2009).

  8. Ideally, we can imagine the following practical syllogism playing out in the reasoning of the speaker: (1) ‘We intend to distribute the magazines’; (2) ‘I am one of us’; (3) ‘I will do my part in distributing the magazines.’ Indeed, the last sentence of the paragraph already suggests how the individual agent can begin to contribute to the collective goal. For a discussion of the relationship between collective intentions and individual participatory intentions, see Tuomela and Miller (1988).

References

  • Altson, W. P. (2007). Religious language. In W. J. Wainwright (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of religion. Oxford University Press. 220–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, E. (1984). The making of a Moonie: Choice or brainwashing? Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckford, J. A. (1975). The trumpet of prophecy: A sociological study of Jehovah’s Witnesses. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchard, A. (2008). Les témoins de Jéhovah par leurs imprimés. Yaoundé: PUCAC.

  • Bratman, M. (1993). Shared intention. Ethics, 104, 97–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2014). Shared agency: A planning theory of acting together. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chryssides, G. D. (2016). Jehovah’s Witnesses: Continuity and change. Ashgate.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duranti, A. (1988). Intentions, language, and social action in a Samoan context. Journal of Pragmatics, 12, 13–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, M. Q. (2018). Truth-conditions and religious language: Introduction. Method & Theory in the Study of Religion, 30(4–5), 321–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, G. S. (1983). Performativity in ritual: The Mianmin case. Man (new Series), 18(2), 346–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1987). Modeling collective belief. Synthese, 73(1), 185–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1996). Walking together: A paradigmatic social phenomenon. In Living together. Rationality, sociality, and obligation. Lanham: Rowman & Littelfield Publishers. 177–194.

  • Gilbert, M. (2003). Ths structure of the social atom: Joint commitment as the foundation of human social behavior. In Schmitt, F. F. (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics. The nature of social reality. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefileld Publishers. 39–64.

  • Gilbert, M. (2007). Searle and collective intentions. In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Intentional acts and institutional facts: Essays on John Searle’s social ontology (pp. 31–47). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2009). Shared intention and personal intentions. Philosophical Studies, 144(1), 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1981). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanegraaff, W. J. (2016). Reconstructing ‘religion’ from the bottom up. Numen, 63(5–6), 576–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holden, A. (2002). Jehovah’s Witnesses: Portrait of a contemporary religious movement. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jankovic, M., & Ludwig, K. (Eds.). (2018). The Routledge handbook of collective intentionality. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, J. S. (2017). Religion is the word, but, what is the thing – If there is one?. On generalized interpretations and epistemic placeholders in the study of religion. Historia Religionum, 9, 17–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kippenberg, H. G. (1983). Diskursive Religionswissenschaft: Gedanken zu einer Religionswissenschaft, die weder auf einer allgemein gültigen Definition von Religion noch auf einer Überlegenheit von Wissenschaft basiert. In Gladigow, B. & Kippenberg, H. G. (Eds.), Neue Ansätze in der Religionswissenschaft. Munich: C.H. Beck. 9–28.

  • Lincoln, B. (1989). Discourse and the construction of society: Comparative studies of myth, ritual, and classification. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2007). Foundations of social reality in collective intentional behavior. In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Intentional acts and institutional facts: Essays on John Searle’s social ontology. Springer. 49–71.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Meijers, A. (2003). Can collective intentionality be individualized? American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 62(1), 167–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quinton, A. (1976). Social objects. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 76, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport, R. A. (1979). The obvious aspects of ritual. In Ecology, meaning, and religion. Berkeley: North Atlantic Books.

  • Rappaport, R. A. (1999). Ritual and religion in the making of humanity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosaldo, M. Z. (1982). The things we do with words: Ilongot speech acts and speech act theory in philosophy. Language in Society, 11(2), 203–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rota, A. (2016). Religion as social reality. A take on the emic–etic debate in light of John Searle’s philosophy of society. Method & Theory in the Study of Religion, 28(4–5), 421–444.

  • Rota, A. (2019). Religion, media, and joint commitment: Jehovah’s Witnesses as a ‘plural subject’. Online – Heidelberg Journal of religions on the Internet, 14 [special issue], 79–107.

  • Rota, A. (in preparation). Collective intentionality and the study of religion. A theoretical and empirical approach. Bloomsbury.

  • Schilbrack, K. (2013). After we deconstruct “religion”, then what? A case for critical realism. Method & Theory in the Study of Religion, 25(1), 107–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schilbrack, K. (2014). Philosophy and the study of religions: A manifesto. Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schilbrack, K. (2017). A realist social ontology of religion. Religion, 47(2), 161–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlieter, J. (2017). Religiöse Symbole im öffentlichen Raum: Symbolwirkung als kollektive Intentionalität einer Deutungsgemeinschaft. Zeitschrift Für Religionswissenschaft, 25(2), 196–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (2012). Shared intentionality and the origins of human communication. In A. Salice (Ed.), Intentionality: Historical and systematic perspectives. Philosophia. 349–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990). Collective intentions and actions. In P. R. Cohen, J. L. Morgan, & M. E. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication (pp. 401–415). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2001). Rationality in action. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2002). Collective intentions and actions. Consciousness and language. Cambridge University Press. 90–105.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2008). Fact and value, ‘is’ and ‘ought,’ and reasons for action. In Philosophy in a new century. Selected Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 161–180.

  • Searle, J. R. (2010). Making the social world: The structure of human civilization. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stark, R., & Iannaccone, L. (1997). Why the Jehovah’s Witnesses grow so rapidly. Journal of Contemporary Religion, 12(2), 133–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stausberg, M. (2010). Distinctions, differentiations, ontology, and non-humans in theories of religion. Method & Theory in the Study of Religion, 22(4), 354–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (1995). The importance of us: A philosophical study of basic social notions. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2003). Collective acceptance, social institutions, and social reality. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 61(1), 123–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2005). We-intentions revised. Philosophical Studies, 125, 327–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007). The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R., & Miller, K. (1988). We-intentions. Philosophical Studies, 53, 367–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R., & Balzer, W. (1999). Collective acceptance and collective social notions. Synthese, 117(2), 175–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyrell, H., Krech, V., & Knoblauch, H. (Eds.). (1998). Religion als Kommunikation. Ergon Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voas, D. (2010). The trumpet sounds retreat. Learning from the Jehovah’s Witnesses. In E. Barker (Ed.), The centrality of religion in social life. Farnham: Ashgate. 117–130.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Rota.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rota, A. (Re)Connecting Analytic Philosophy and Empirical Research: The Example of Ritual Speech Acts and Religious Collectivities. SOPHIA 61, 79–92 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00899-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00899-5

Keywords

Navigation