Skip to main content
Log in

On Jamesian ‘Passionally Caused Atheistic Belief’: a Reply to Cockayne and Warman

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Cockayne and Warman recently argued that William James’s argument as stated in his lecture ‘The Will to Believe’ can be reconstructed so as to justify a ‘passionately caused atheism.’ I will argue that this reading misses the important point of James’s argument, which is the attempt to show that our initial atheistic passional tendencies become untenable once we are aware of the beneficial consequences we might obtain from forming the belief that God exists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. It is true that in some of his texts, James displayed something of an ambiguous opinion regarding immortality. Thus, in his lecture Human Immortality: Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine (1897), James said of himself that he was not ‘known as an enthusiastic messenger of the future life’ (James 1897 [1982], 78), while also claiming that ‘Immortality is one of the great spiritual needs of man’ (James 1897 [1982], 77) and devoting the entire lecture to defending the coherency of immortality, even accepting the brain-dependence of the mind. Similarly, in his The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (1902), James claimed that ‘The whole interest of the question of God’s existence seems to me to lie in the consequences for particulars which that existence may be expected to entail. ... The difference in natural “fact” which most of us would assign as the first difference which the existence of God ought to make would, I imagine, be personal immortality. Religion, in fact, for the great majority of our own race means immortality, and nothing else. God is the producer of immortality; and whoever has doubts of immortality is written down as an atheist without farther trial’ (James 1902 [2002], 403–404). However, James added that the question of immortality was ‘a secondary point’ regarding the themes discussed in The Varieties of Religious Experience (James 1902 [2002], 404), while also expressing his sympathy towards the possibility of immortality, even when refraining from conclusively affirming human immortality given the lack of sufficient factual evidence for its support (i.e., ‘Yet I sympathize with the urgent impulse to be present ourselves, and in the conflict of impulses, both of them so vague yet both of them noble, I know not how to decide. It seems to me that it is emminently a case for facts to testify. Facts, I think, are yet lacking to prove “spirit-return” ... I consequently leave the matter open, with this brief word to save the reader from a possible perplexity as to why immortality got no mention in the body of this book’ (James 1902 [2002], 404)). Less ambiguous was James in 1904, when he recognized that he had ‘never keenly’ believed in personal immortality, although he confessed that he had come to believe in it ‘more strongly as I grow older. ... Because I am just getting fit to live’ (James 1904 [1920], 214). James, then, showed some resistance to fully endorsing the belief that we will, in fact, enjoy some kind of personal immortality. However, as the previous quotes show, the reason why James does not conclusively affirm human immortality relies exclusively on evidential terms, because he had not found conclusive and indisputable evidence that such a thing was actually going to occur. The point to emphasize is, then, that James did not deny the possibility of human immortality and, most importantly, he did not question its pragmatic value and therefore its role in making theism the only attractive option to us.

References

  • Cockayne, J., & Warman, J. (2019). The will not to believe. Sophia, 58, 511–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1897 [1979]). The will to believe. In W. James, The will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy. Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press, 13–33.

  • James, W. (1897 [1982]). Human immortality: two supposed objections to the doctrine. In W. James, Essays in religion and morality. Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press, 75–101.

  • James, W. (1902 [2002]). The varieties of religious experience: a study in human nature. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1904 [1920]). Answers to the Pratt questionnaire on religious belief. In H. James (Ed.), The letters of William James (Vol. II, pp. 212–214). Boston (Massachusetts): The Atlantic Monthly Press.

  • Lougheed, K. (2019). On the will not to believe and axiological atheism: a reply to Cockayne and Warman. Sophia, 58, 743–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Oya.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Oya, A. On Jamesian ‘Passionally Caused Atheistic Belief’: a Reply to Cockayne and Warman. SOPHIA 60, 481–485 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00832-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00832-w

Keywords

Navigation