Abstract
Crother and Murray (Cladistics 31: 573–574, 2015) criticize the statement by Assis (Cladistics 30: 240–242, 2014) that phylogenetic hypotheses are amenable to testing but not falsification. The claims by both sets of authors are based on long-standing misconceptions about testing developed within systematics. Testing phylogenetic hypotheses confuses the inferences of those hypotheses by way of abductive reasoning with their being tested via induction. Cladograms lack the causal details of the different hypotheses implied by those diagrams to make testing feasible, and falsification has been shown to be problematic for historical sciences.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.


References
Achinstein, P. (1970). Inference to scientific laws. In R. H. Stuewer (Ed.), Volume V: Historical and philosophical perspectives of science (pp. 87–111). Minnesota: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, University of Minnesota Press.
Aliseda, A. (2006). Abductive reasoning: Logical investigations into discovery and explanation. Dordrecht: Springer.
Ariew, A. (2003). Ernst Mayr’s ‘ultimate/proximate’ distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 553–565.
Assis, L. C. S. (2014). Testing evolutionary hypotheses: From Willi Hennig to Angiosperm phylogeny group. Cladistics, 30, 240–242.
Baker, V. R. (1996). Hypotheses and geomorphological reasoning. In B. L. Rhoads & C. E. Thorn (Eds.), The scientific nature of geomorphology: Proceedings of the 27th Binghamton symposium in geomorphology held 27–29 September 1996 (pp. 57–85). New York: Wiley.
Barnes, E. (1994). Why P rather than Q? The curiosities of fact and foil. Philosophical Studies, 73, 35–53.
Beatty, J. (1994). The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr. Biolology and Philosophy, 9, 333–356.
Ben-Menahem, Y. (1990). The inference to the best explanation. Erkenntnis, 33, 319–344.
Bromberger, S. (1966). Why-questions. In R. G. Colodny (Ed.), Mind and cosmos: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy. University of Pittsburgh series in the philosophy of science, 3 (pp. 86–111). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Brower, A. V. Z., & de Pinna, M. C. C. (2012). Homology and errors. Cladistics, 28, 529–538.
Cleland, C. E. (2001). Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method. Geology, 29, 987–990.
Cleland, C. E. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 474–496.
Cleland, C. E. (2009). Philosophical issues in natural history and historiography. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 44–62). Malden: Wiley.
Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 551–582.
Cleland, C. E. (2013). Common cause explanation and the search for a smoking gun. The Geological Society of America Special Papers, 502, 1–9.
Crother, B. I., & Murray, C. M. (2015). Testable but not falsifiable? Cladistics, 31, 573–574.
Curd, M. V. (1980). The logic of discovery: An analysis of three approaches. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery, logic and rationality (pp. 201–219). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.
Dawid, R. (2013). String theory and the scientific method. New York: Cambridge University Press.
de Queiroz, K. (2014). Popperian corroboration and phylogenetics. Systematic Biology, 63, 1018–1022.
de Queiroz, K., & Poe, S. (2001). Philosophy and phylogenetic inference: A comparison of likelihood and parsimony methods in the context of Karl Popper’s writings on corroboration. Systematic Biology, 50, 305–321.
de Queiroz, K., & Poe, S. (2003). Failed refutations: Further comments on parsimony and likelihood methods and their relationship to Popper’s degree of corroboration. Systematic Biology, 52, 322–330.
de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.
de Regt, H. W., Leonelli, S., & Eigner, K. (2009). Focusing on scientific understanding. In H. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 1–17). Pittsburgh: University of Press.
Douven, I. (2002). Testing inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 130, 355–377.
Egan, M. G. (2006). Support versus corroboration. Journal of Biomedical Informatics, 39, 72–85.
Eldredge, N., & Cracraft, J. (1980). Phylogenetic patterns and the evolutionary process: Method and theory in comparative biology. New York: Columbia University Press.
Faith, D. P. (2004). From species to supertrees: Popperian corroboration and some current controversies in systematics. Australian Systematic Botany, 17, 1–16.
Faith, D. P. (2006). Science and philosophy for molecular systematics: Which is the cart and which is the horse? Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, 38, 553–557.
Faith, D. P., & Cranston, P. S. (1992). Probability, parsimony, and Popper. Systematic Biology, 41, 252–257.
Faith, D. P., Köhler, F., Puslednik, L., & Ballard, J. W. O. (2011). Phylogenies with corroboration assessment. Zootaxa, 2946, 52–56.
Faith, D. P., & Trueman, J. W. H. (2001). Towards an inclusive philosophy for phylogenetic inference. Systematic Biology, 50, 331–350.
Fann, K. T. (1970). Peirce’s theory of abduction. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Farris, J. S., Kluge, A. G., & Carpenter, J. M. (2001). Popper and likelihood versus “Popper*”. Systematic Biology, 50, 438–444.
Fitzhugh, K. (2005a). Les bases philosophiques de l’inférence phylogénétique: une vue d’ensemble. Biosystema, 24, 83–105.
Fitzhugh, K. (2005b). The inferential basis of species hypotheses: The solution to defining the term ‘species’. Marine Ecology, 26, 155–165.
Fitzhugh, K. (2006a). The abduction of phylogenetic hypotheses. Zootaxa, 1145, 1–110.
Fitzhugh, K. (2006b). The ‘requirement of total evidence’ and its role in phylogenetic systematics. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 309–351.
Fitzhugh, K. (2006c). The philosophical basis of character coding for the inference of phylogenetic hypotheses. Zoologica Scripta, 35, 261–286.
Fitzhugh, K. (2008a). Fact, theory, test and evolution. Zoologica Scripta, 37, 109–113.
Fitzhugh, K. (2008b). Abductive inference: Implications for ‘Linnean’ and ‘phylogenetic’ approaches for representing biological systematization. Evolutionary Biology, 35, 52–82.
Fitzhugh, K. (2008c). Clarifying the role of character loss in phylogenetic inference. Zoologica Scripta, 37, 561–569.
Fitzhugh, K. (2009). Species as explanatory hypotheses: Refinements and implications. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 201–248.
Fitzhugh, K. (2010). Evidence for evolution versus evidence for intelligent design: Parallel confusions. Evolutionary Biology, 37, 68–92.
Fitzhugh, K. (2012). The limits of understanding in biological systematics. Zootaxa, 3435, 40–67.
Fitzhugh, K. (2013). Defining ‘species’, ‘biodiversity’, and ‘conservation’ by their transitive relations. In I. Y. Pavlinov (Ed.), The species problem—Ongoing problems (pp. 93–130). New York: InTech.
Fitzhugh, K. (2014). Character mapping and cladogram comparison versus the requirement of total evidence: Does it matter for polychaete systematics? Memoires of Museum Victoria, 71, 67–78.
Fitzhugh, K. (2015). What are species? Or, on asking the wrong question. The Festivus, 47, 229–239.
Fitzhugh, K. (2016). Dispelling five myths about hypothesis testing in biological systematics. Organisms Diversity and Evolution,. doi:10.1007/s13127-016-0274-6.
Franz, N. M. (2005). Outline of an explanatory account of cladistic practice. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 489–515.
Gaffney, E. S. (1979). An introduction to the logic of phylogeny reconstruction. In J. Cracraft & N. Eldredge (Eds.), Phylogenetic analysis and paleontology (pp. 79–111). New York: Columbia University Press.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003). Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Grandcolas, P., Deleporte, P. & Desutter-Grandcolas, L. (1997). Testing evolutionary processes with phylogenetic patterns: Test power and test limitations. In P. Grandcolas (Ed.) The origin of biodiversity in insects: Phylogenetic tests of evolutionary scenarios. Paris: Mémoires du Muséum National d’Histoire Naturelle, 173, 53–71.
Grant, T., & Kluge, A. G. (2008). Clade support measures and their adequacy. Cladistics, 24, 1051–1064.
Hacking, I. (2001). An introduction to probability and inductive logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Harman, G. H. (1965). Inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.
Hausman, D. M. (1998). Causal asymmetries. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Helfenbein, G. K., & DeSalle, R. (2005). Falsifications and corroborations: Karl Popper’s influence on systematics. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, 35, 271–280.
Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.
Hennig, W. (1966). Phylogenetic systematics. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The nature of science. New York: Oxford University Press.
Jeffares, B. (2008). Testing times: Regularities in the historical sciences. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39, 469–475.
Josephson, J. R., & Josephson, S. G. (Eds.). (1994). Abductive inference: Computation, philosophy, technology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kluge, A. G. (1997a). Sophisticated falsification and research cycles: Consequences for differential character weighting in phylogenetic systematics. Zoologica Scripta, 26, 349–360.
Kluge, A. G. (1997b). Testability and the refutation and corroboration of cladistic hypotheses. Cladistics, 13, 81–96.
Kluge, A. G. (1999). The science of phylogenetic systematics: Explanation, prediction, and test. Cladistics, 15, 429–436.
Kluge, A. G. (2001). Philosophical conjectures and their refutation. Systematic Biology, 50, 322–330.
Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science, 334, 1512–1516.
Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. New York: Routledge.
Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason, and science: Processes of discovery and explanation. New York: Kluwer Academic.
Mahner, M., & Bunge, M. (1997). Foundations of biophilosophy. New York: Springer.
Marwick, P. (1999). Interrogatives and contrasts in explanation theory. Philosophical Studies, 96, 183–204.
Mayo, D. G. (1991). Novel evidence and severe tests. Philosophy of Science, 58, 523–552.
Mayo, D. G. (1996). Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Mayo, D. G. (2005). Peircean induction and the error-correcting thesis. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 41, 299–319.
Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science, 131, 1501–1506.
Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Mayr, E. (1993). Proximate and ultimate causation. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 95–98.
Mayr, E. (1994). Response to John Beatty. Biology and Philosophy, 9, 359–371.
McMullin, E. (1995). The inference that makes science. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
Nickles, T. (1980). Introductory essay: Scientific discovery and the future of philosophy of science. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery, logic and rationality (pp. 1–59). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Nola, R., & Sankey, H. (2007). Theories of scientific method: An introduction. Ithaca: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Norton, J. D. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647–670.
Paavola, S. (2012). On the origin of ideas: An abductionist approach to discovery. Saarbrücken: Lap Lambert Academic Publishing.
Peirce, C. S. (1878). Illustrations of the logic of science. Sixth paper.—Deduction, induction, and hypothesis. Popular Science Monthly, 13, 470–482.
Peirce, C. S. (1931). In: C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 1: Principles of Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1932). In: C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 2: Elements of Logic. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1933a). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 3: Exact Logic. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1933b). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 4: The Simplest Mathematics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1934). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 5: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1935). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 6: Scientific Metaphysics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1958a). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 7: Science and Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1958b). In: A. Burks (Ed.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume 8: Correspondence and Bibliography. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.
Popper, K. R. (1962). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. New York: Basic Books.
Popper, K. R. (1971). The open society and its enemies, Volume 2: Hegel and Marx. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Popper, K. R. (1983). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. New York: Oxford University Press.
Popper, K. R. (1988). The poverty of historicism. New York: Routledge.
Popper, K. R. (1992). Realism and the aim of science. New York: Routledge.
Psillos, S. (2002). Simply the best: A case for abduction. In A. C. Kakas & F. Sadri (Eds.), Computational logic: Logic programming and beyond (pp. 605–625). New York: Springer.
Psillos, S. (2006). Underdetermination thesis, Duhem-Quine thesis. In D. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (2nd ed., Vol. 9, pp. 575–578). Detroit: Macmillan.
Psillos, S. (2007). Philosophy of science A-Z. Edinburgh: University Press.
Psillos, S. (2011). An explorer upon untrodden ground: Peirce on abduction. In D. Gabbay, S. Hartmann, & J. Woods (Eds.), The handbook of the history of logic (Vol. 10, pp. 117–151)., inductive logic Oxford: Elsevier.
Reilly, F. E. (1970). Charles Peirce’s theory of scientific method. New York: Fordham University Press.
Rescher, N. (1970). Scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.
Rescher, N. (1978). Peirce’s philosophy of science: Critical studies in his theory of induction and scientific method. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Rieppel, O. (1988). Fundamentals of comparative biology. Boston: Birkhäuser Verlag.
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Scholl, R., & Pigliucci, M. (2014). The proximate-ultimate distinction and evolutionary developmental biology: Causal irrelevance versus explanatory abstraction. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 653–670.
Schuh, R. T. (2000). Biological systematics: Principles and applications. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Schuh, R. T., & Brower, A. V. Z. (2009). Biological systematics: Principles and applications (2nd ed.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Schurz, G. (2005). Explanations in science and the logic of why-questions: Discussion of the Halonen–Hintikka-approach and alternative proposal. Synthese, 143, 149–178.
Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164, 201–234.
Siddall, M. E., & Kluge, A. G. (1997). Probabilism and phylogenetic inference. Cladistics, 13, 313–336.
Sintonen, M. (2004). Reasoning to hypotheses: Where do questions come? Foundation of Science, 9, 249–266.
Sober, E. (1986). Explanatory presupposition. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 143–149.
Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution, and inference. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Strahler, A. N. (1992). Understanding science: An introduction to concepts and issues. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.
Thagard, P. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Thagard, P. (2004). Rationality and science. In A. Mele & P. Rawlings (Eds.), Handbook of rationality (pp. 363–379). New York: Oxford University Press.
Tucker, A. (2004). Our knowledge of the past: A philosophy of historiography. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Tucker, A. (2011). Historical science, over- and underdetermined: A study of Darwin’s inference of origins. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 805–829.
Turner, D. (2007). Making prehistory: Historical science and the scientific realism debate. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Turner, D. (2013). Historical geology: Methodology and metaphysics. Geological Society of America Special Paper, 502, 1–9.
Van Fraassen, B. C. (1990). The scientific image. New York: Clarendon Press.
Walton, D. (2004). Abductive reasoning. Tuscaloosa: The University of Alabama Press.
Wenzel, J. W. (1997). When is a phylogenetic test good enough? In P. Grandcolas (Ed.) The origin of biodiversity in insects: Phylogenetic tests of evolutionary scenarios. Paris: Mémoires du Muséum National d’Histoire Naturelle, 173, 31–45.
Wheeler, Q. D. (2004). Taxonomic triage and the poverty of phylogeny. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 359, 571–583.
Wheeler, Q. D. (2010). Do we need to describe, name, and classify all species? In D. M. Williams & S. Knapp (Eds.), Beyond cladistics: The branching of a paradigm (pp. 67–75). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Wheeler, Q., & Hamilton, A. (2014). The new systematics, the new taxonomy, and the future of biodiversity studies. In A. Hamilton (Ed.), The evolution of phylogenetic systematics (pp. 287–301). Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Wiley, E. O. (1975). Karl R. Popper, systematics, and classification: A reply to Walter Bock and other evolutionary taxonomists. Systematic Zoology, 24, 233–243.
Wiley, E. O., & Lieberman, B. S. (2011). Phylogenetics: Theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Oxford: Wiley.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of Interest
The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Fitzhugh, K. Phylogenetic Hypotheses: Neither Testable Nor Falsifiable. Evol Biol 43, 257–266 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-016-9381-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-016-9381-8
Keywords
- Abductive reasoning
- Cladogram
- Falsification
- Phylogenetic systematics
- Testing