Abstract
The suffering of nonhuman animals has become a noted factor in deciding public policy and legislative change. Yet, despite this growing concern, skepticism toward such suffering is still surprisingly common. This paper analyzes the merits of the skeptical approach, both in its moderate and extreme forms. In the first part it is claimed that the type of criterion for verification concerning the mental states of other animals posed by skepticism is overly (and, in the case of extreme skepticism, illogically) demanding. Resting on Wittgenstein and Husserl, it is argued that skepticism relies on a misguided epistemology and, thus, that key questions posed by it face the risk of absurdity. In the second part of the paper it is suggested that, instead of skepticism, empathy together with intersubjectivity be adopted. Edith Stein’s take on empathy, along with contemporary findings, are explored, and the claim is made that it is only via these two methods of understanding that the suffering of nonhuman animals can be perceived.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
“Animal suffering” is here defined as a holistic affective state with high intensity (see Aaltola 2012).
Not all are as favorable toward this approach. For instance, the skeptic Peter Carruthers maintains that “[i]t really is something of a scandal that people’s intuitions, in this domain, are given any weight at all” (2000, 199).
Using Nussbaum’s reading, Fox and McLean have argued that, within animal experimentation, lack of perception may often lead to similarly monstrous results. In these situations, experiments have allowed researchers’ “perceptions … [to] become shallow and faint; they don’t see what is there to be seen because they ignore their emotional and imaginative responses and what these responses should reveal to them”—they are taking part in a “de-sensitised reading process” (Fox and McLean 2008, 167 and 168).
For Husserl, too, empathy was crucial, for it enables one to perceive others as fellow subjects rather than as physical bodies—empathy forms “our primary form of experience of others, as others” (Smith 2007, 228).
To use Peter Goldie’s words: “Empathy is a process or procedure by which a person centrally imagines the narrative (the thoughts, feelings and emotions) of another person” (Goldie 2000, 195).
Yet, saying this, differences cannot be sidelined, and it is possible that they hide a great deal of animal suffering from human perception (see NRC 2009; Aaltola 2012). Therefore, empathy toward other animals (and other human beings) must always be accompanied by a sense of regard for the specificity of other individuals.
References
Aaltola, E. 2012. Animal suffering: Philosophy and culture. London: Palgrave MacMillan.
Baron-Cohen, S. 2011. Zero degrees of empathy: A new theory of human cruelty. London: Penguin.
Baron-Cohen, S., and S. Wheelwright. 2004. The empathy quotient: An investigation of adults with Asperger Syndrome or high functioning autism and normal sex differences. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 34(2): 163–175.
Bekoff, M. 2000. Animal emotions: Exploring passionate natures. BioScience 50(10): 861–870.
Carman, T. 2008. Merleau-Ponty. London: Routledge.
Carruthers, P. 1992. The animals issue: Moral theory in practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. 2000. Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Crist, E. 1999. Images of animals: Anthropocentrism and animal mind. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Dawkins, M.S. 2003. Animal minds and animal emotions. In The animal ethics reader, ed. S.J. Armstrong and R.G. Botzler, 94–99. London: Routledge.
De Waal, F. 2006. Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved. Ed. S. Macedo and J. Ober. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
De Waal, F.B.M. 2008. Putting the altruism back into altruism: The evolution of empathy. Annual Review of Psychology 59: 279–300.
Decety, J., and P.L. Jackson. 2006. A social-neuroscience perspective on empathy. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15(2): 54–58.
Dennett, D.C. 1998. Brainchildren: Essays on designing minds. Cambridge: Bradford and MIT Press.
Diamond, C. 2004. Eating meat and eating people. In Animal rights: Current debates and new directions, ed. C.R. Sunstein and M.C. Nussbaum, 93–107. London: Routledge.
Donovan, J. 2007. Attention to suffering: Sympathy as a basis for ethical treatment of animals. In The feminist care tradition in animal ethics: A reader, ed. J. Donovan and C.J. Adams, 174–197. New York: Columbia University Press.
Fox, M.A., and L. McLean. 2008. Animals in moral space. In Animal subjects: An ethical reader in a posthuman world, ed. J. Castricano, 145–176. Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.
Gaita, R. 2002. The philosopher’s dog: Friendships with animals. London: Routledge.
Gallagher, S. 2001. The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or interaction? In Between ourselves: Second-person issues in the study of consciousness, ed. E. Thompson, 83–108. Thorverton: Imprint Academic.
Goldie, P. 2000. The emotions: A philosophical exploration. Oxford: Clarendon.
Goldman, A.I. 1995. Simulation and interpersonal utility. Ethics 105(4): 709–726.
Gruen, L. 2007. Empathy and vegetarian commitments. In The feminist care tradition in animal ethics: A reader, ed. J. Donovan and C.J. Adams, 333–343. New York: Columbia University Press.
Hoffman, M.L. 1990. Empathy and justice motivation. Motivation and Emotion 14(2): 151–172.
Holton, R., and R. Langton. 1998. Empathy and animal ethics. In Singer and his critics, ed. D. Jamieson, 209–232. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Hourdequin, M. 2012. Empathy, shared intentionality, and motivation by moral reasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15(3): 403–419.
Hume, D. 1975. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Husserl, E. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second book: Studies in the phenomenology of constitution. Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Originally published as Ideen zur einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1952).
Jamieson, D. 2002. Morality’s progress: Essays on humans, other animals, and the rest of nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kennedy, J.S. 1992. The new anthropomorphism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge. Originally published as Phénomènologie de la perception (Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1945).
National Research Council (NRC). 2009. Recognition and alleviation of pain in laboratory animals. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
Nilsson, P. 2003. Empathy and emotions: On the notion of empathy as emotional sharing. Ph.D. diss., Umeå University, Umeå Studies in Philosophy 7. http://umu.diva-portal.org/smash/get/diva2:144419/FULLTEXT01.pdf.
Nussbaum, M.C. 2001. The upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pick, A. 2011. Creaturely poetics: Animality and vulnerability in literature and film. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rollin, B.E. 2003a. Animal pain. In The animal ethics reader, ed. S.J. Armstrong and R.G. Botzler, 86–91. London: Routledge.
Rollin, B.E. 2003b. Scientific ideology, anthropomorphism, anecdote, and ethics. In The animal ethics reader, ed. S.J. Armstrong and R.G. Botzler, 67–74. London: Routledge.
Searle, J.R. 1994. Animal minds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19(1): 206–219.
Smith, D.W. 2007. Husserl. London: Routledge.
Smuts, B. 1999. Reflections. In The lives of animals, ed. J.M. Coetzee, 107–120. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Stein, E. 1989. On the problem of empathy: The collected works of Edith Stein. Trans. W. Stein. Washington, DC: ISC Publishing. Originally published as Zum Problem der Einfühlung (Halle: Buchdrucheri des Waisenhauses, 1917).
Thompson, E. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. In Between ourselves: Second-person issues in the study of consciousness, ed. E. Thompson, 1–32. Thorverton: Imprint Academic.
Weil, S. 2002. Gravity and grace. London: Routledge.
Weil, S. 2005. An anthology. Ed. S. Miles. London: Penguin.
Weil, K. 2012. Thinking animals: Why animal studies now? New York: Columbia University Press.
Wemelsfelder, F. 1999. The problem of animal subjectivity and its consequences for the scientific measurement of animal suffering. In Attitudes to animals: Views in animal welfare, ed. F.L. Dolins, 37–53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. 1958. Philosophical investigations, 2nd edition. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. 1980. Remarks on the philosophy of psychology, volume II. Trans. C.G. Luckhardt and M.A.E. Aue, ed. G.H. VonWright and H. Nyman. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Zahavi, D. 2008. Simulation, projection and empathy. Consciousness and Cognition 17(2): 514–522.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Aaltola, E. Skepticism, Empathy, and Animal Suffering. Bioethical Inquiry 10, 457–467 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-013-9481-4
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-013-9481-4