Skip to main content
Log in

Storks, Cabbage Patches, and the Right to Procreate

  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I examine the prevailing assumption that there is a right to procreate and question whether there exists a coherent notion of such a right. I argue that we should question any and all procreative activities, not just alternative procreative means and contexts. I suggest that clinging to the assumption of a right to procreate prevents serious scrutiny of reproductive behavior and that, instead of continuing to embrace this assumption, attempts should be made to provide a proper foundation for it. I argue that the focus of procreative activities and discourse on reproductive ethics should be on obligations instead of rights, as rights talk tends to obfuscate recognition of obligations toward others, particularly those who bear the most significant burdens of the procreative process. I examine some possible foundations of a right to procreate as well as John Robertson’s thoughtful account of “procreative liberty” but conclude that at the present time there exists no compelling account of a right to procreate. Finally, I conclude that in the absence of a satisfactory account of a right to procreate, we should refrain from grounding practices or polices on the assumption that there is such a right.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, State of Wisconsin v. David W. Oakley, wherein a condition of Mr. Oakley’s parole was to refrain from further procreation until he had paid his child-support debt. SCOTUS denied certiorari on October 7, 2002. More recently, Justice Marilyn L. O’Connor of the New York Family Court, Monroe County, ordered a woman to refrain from having children, lest she be jailed. See In re Anna E. (2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2843).

  2. In response an earlier version of this paper, Grant Gillett brought to my attention an example of this type of scenario. He pointed out that government-mandated use of a certain type of IUD in China has led to a 90% sterility rate among women who were forced to use the IUD.

References

  1. Bristow, J.(2005). What’s wrong with the world’s oldest mum? Spiked Online [Internet] 2005 Jan 18 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.spiked-online.com/Articles/0000000CA884.htm.

  2. Philipkoski, K. (2005). No magic for older moms. Wired News [Internet]. 2005 Jan 19 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.wired.com/news/medtech/0,1286,66322,00.html.

  3. Shilling, J. (2005). Were Adriana Iliescu a man, the press would applaud her. Times Online [Internet] 2005 Jan 21[cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.timesonline.co.uk/article/0,,7-1448942,00.html.

  4. Caplan, A. L. (2005). How old is too old to have a baby: Fertility clinics should implement age limits. Bioethics on MSNBC (Internet) 2005 Jan 24 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.bioethics.net/articles.php?viewCat=2&articleId=178.

  5. Archard, D. (2004).Wrongful life. Philosophy, 79, 403–420.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Bayles, M. D. (1976). Harm to the unconceived. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5, 292–304.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Cohen, C. B. (1997). The morality of knowingly conceiving children with serious conditions: An expanded “wrongful life” standard. In N. Fotion, J. C. Heller (Eds.), Contingent future persons (pp. 27–40). Boston, MA: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to others. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Glover, J. (2006). Choosing children: Genes, disability, and design. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. O’Neill, O. (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Purdy, L. M. (1996). Reproducing persons: Issues in feminist bioethics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Robertson, J. A. (1994). Children of choice. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Shanner, L. (1995). The right to procreate: When rights claims have gone wrong. McGill Law Journal, 40, 823–874. August.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Steinbock, B. (1986). The logical case for “wrongful life”. Hastings Center Report, 16(2), 15–20.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  16. Steinbock, B., & McClamrock, R. (1994). When is birth unfair to the child? Hastings Center Report, 24(6), 15–21. Nov–Dec.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Finer, L. B., & Henshaw, S. K. (2006). Disparities in rates of unintended pregnancy in the United States, 1994 and 2001. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health, 38(2), 90–96.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Trounson, R., & Becerra, H. (2005). USC case shows limits of laws to save babies. In Los Angeles Times, (October 16 issue, Sect. B:1).

  19. Shaw, M. N. (2005). Safe surrender law seeks reduction in child deaths. The Franklin Press Online [Internet] 2005 Oct 18 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.thefranklinpress.com/articles/2005/10/18/news/news03.txt.

  20. Dailard, C. (2000) The drive to enact ‘infant abandonment’ laws—A rush to judgment? The Guttmacher Report on Public Policy [Internet] 2000 Aug [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.agi-usa.org/pubs/tgr/03/4/gr030401.html.

  21. Wilson, P. (1997) Medicine: Welfare in California. The Economist, 342(8000), 26–27.

  22. BBC News Online (2004). Pay addicts not to have children. [Internet] 2004 Mar 13 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/scotland/3508084.stm.

  23. Rao, R. (1998). Reconceiving privacy: Relationships and reproductive technology. UCLA Law Review, 45, 1077–1123. Apr.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s dominion. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Coleman, C. H. (2002). Assisted reproductive technologies and the constitution. Fordham Urban Law Journal, 30, 57–70. Nov.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Sumner, W. (1987). The moral foundations of rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Warnock, M. (2003). Making babies: Is there a right to have children? New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Mulrine, A. (2004). Making babies. US News and World Report, 137(10), 60–64, 66.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  29. Gurmankin, A. D, Caplan, A. L., & Braverman, A. M. (2005). Screening practices and beliefs of assisted reproductive technology programs. Fertility and Sterility, 83(1), 61–67. Jan.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  30. Silver, L., & Silver, S. R. (1998). Confused heritage and the absurdity of genetic ownership. Harvard Journal of Law and Technology, 11(3), 593–618.

    Google Scholar 

  31. General Assembly of the United Nations (1948). Universal declaration of human rights. [Internet] 1948 [cited 2006 Nov 25]. Available from: http://www.un.org/Overview/rights.html.

  32. Brazier, M. (1998). Reproductive rights: Feminism or patriarchy. In J. Harris, S. Holm, (Eds.), The future of human reproduction. (pp. 66–76). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Spriggs, M. (2005). Autonomy and patients’ decisions. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  34. O’Neill, O. (1989). Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Kant, I. (1952). The Science of Right [translated by W. Hastie] 1790. In R. M. Hutchins, M. Adler (Eds.), Great books of the western world, vol. 42 (pp. 397–458). Chicago: Encyclopedia Brittanica.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Mill, J. S. (1975). On liberty. In D. Spitz (Ed.). New York: Norton.

  37. Robertson, J. A. (2004). Procreative liberty and harm to offspring in assisted reproduction. American Journal of Law and Medicine, 30(1), 7–40.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. Atwood, M. (1986). The handmaid’s tale. London: Cape.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank JBI’s anonymous reviewers and Editor Christopher Jordens for insightful comments and helpful guidance in revising this article. Thank you also to Dale E. Miller for his valuable comments and recommendations on an earlier version of this paper.

Competing interests

None declared.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yvette E. Pearson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pearson, Y.E. Storks, Cabbage Patches, and the Right to Procreate. Bioethical Inquiry 4, 105–115 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-007-9047-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-007-9047-4

Keywords

Navigation