Skip to main content

Official Disobedience: Bureaucrats & Unjust Laws

Abstract

A legitimate expectation in a liberal democracy is that public officials enforce the law regardless of its content; when they don’t do so, their actions tend to be publicly condemned. This expectation puts street-level bureaucrats in a moral dilemma when they consider that a certain law is unjust: either they don’t enforce the law and violate their duties to the citizenry, or they enforce it and become complicit in injustices. This paper argues for the legal permission of public officials to disregard legal mandates for moral reasons. Call it official disobedience. Contrary to common intuitions, I show that official disobedience would foster the principles of and improve governance in liberal democracies: it accommodates public officials’ personal autonomy and yields three main democratic benefits. First, information about the outcomes of the law would become available for lawmakers; second, in the aggregate, it would protect citizens from injustices; third, it would improve the moral character of bureaucrats.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes

  1. Political scientists often assume that a main characteristic of the administrative state is the principal-agent relation that exists between citizens and public officials, see Miller 2005. However, informed citizens know that certain bureaucrats have a certain degree of discretion regarding the enforcement of the law (e.g., prosecutors). This paper focuses on street-level bureaucrats, those who are not elected or formally appointed, but merely hired, and who tend to be at the lowest levels of the administrative state.

  2. See Heath 2020, Chap. 6.

  3. Admittedly, it sounds rather paradoxical to say that there is legal permission to disobey the law. “Officials disobedience” must be understood as a label to refer to the disregard or omission to enforce the law, not really an act of disobedience. Yet, I opt for this label to keep the parallelism between “civil disobedience” and “official disobedience.” I argue that both moral rights have similar foundations in a liberal democracy. I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this clarification.

  4. I follow Brownlee’s understanding of a moral right of conscience as “essentially a claim-right that others not interfere with our carrying out our responsibilities” (2012, 119).

  5. Following Raz (1979), I take for granted that people have no moral obligation to obey illegitimate regimes.

  6. Estlund (2007, 218) does acknowledge that there might be an exception if Jason has first-hand knowledge that the inmate is innocent.

  7. See Arendt 2006.

  8. For other arguments against the voluntarist objection, see Brownlee (2012, 111–112).

  9. There might be cases in which this is justified, but they tend to be exceptional.

  10. Yet, if Jason uses the key to open the inmate’s cell, he is using public power for advancing his moral convictions, hence this is not an act of official disobedience.

  11. See Schiffrin’s (2000) notion of accommodation.

  12. I leave open the possibility that, in some complicated cases, the justification of official disobedience can be scrutinized by the judicial power.

  13. I leave the specifics open.

  14. Pierre Rosanvallon (2008) talks about the legitimacy of proximity.

  15. For the relation between group size and the collective decision-making cost, see Buchanan and Tullock (1962).

  16. Regarding the difficulties of reaching a supermajority in collective decisions, I follow Buchanan and Tullock (1962).

References

  • American Bar Association. 2017. The Criminal Justice Standards for the Prosecution Function. https://www.americanbar.org/groups/criminal_justice/standards/ProsecutionFunctionFourthEdition (Accessed June 2021).

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2006. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. New York, NY: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. Nicomachean Ethics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2019. When All Else Fails: The Ethics of Resistance of State Injustice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brownlee, Kimberly. 2010. Responsibilities of Criminal Justice Officials. Journal of Applied Philosophy 27: 123–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownlee, Kimberly. 2012. Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. In The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Vol. 3. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, Allen. 2002. Political Legitimacy and Democracy. Ethics 112: 689–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ceva, Emanuela and Maria Paola Ferretti. 2018. Political Corruption, Individual Behavior and the Quality of Institutions. Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 17: 216–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, Thomas. 1999. Justice and Disagreement at the Foundations of Political Authority. Ethics 110: 165–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, Thomas. 2007. The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero. 1887. De Officiis. Translated, introduction, and notes by A.P. Peabody. Boston, MA: Little Brown, & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deci, Edward L. and Richard M. Ryan. 2012. Motivation, Personality, and Development Within Embedded Social Contexts: An Overview of Self-Determination Theory. In The Oxford Handbook of Human Motivation, edited by Richard M. Ryan: 85–108.

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2007. On Following Orders in an Unjust War. Journal of Political Philosophy 15(2): 213–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Barry J., Greg J. Coman, and Robb O. Stanley. 1992. The Police Personality: Type A Behavior and Trait Anxiety. Journal of Criminal Justice 20: 429–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert. 1988. Reasons for Welfare: The Political Theory of the Welfare State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, Joseph. 2020. The Machinery of Government: Public Administration and the Liberal State. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, Michael. 2018. The Duty to Disregard the Law. Criminal Law & Philosophy 12: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, Martin Luther, Jr. 2018. Letter from Birmingham Jail. Penguin Modern. London, England: Penguin Classics.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsky, Michael. 2010. Street-Level Bureaucracy, 30th Anniversary Edition: Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Service. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matjie, Mokgata. 2018. Bureaucracy and Personality. In Global Encyclopedia of Public Administration, Public Policy, and Governance, edited by A. Farazmand. Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31816-5_674-1 (Accessed June 2021).

  • Miller, Gary. 2005. The Political Evolution of Principal-Agent Models. Annual Review of Political Science 8: 203–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monaghan, Jake. 2018. On Enforcing Unjust Laws in a Just Society. The Philosophical Quarterly 68: 758–778.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Police Reform Act 2002. https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2002/30/contents (Accessed June 2021).

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1979. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosanvallon, Pierre. 2008. La Légitimité démocratique: Impartialité, Réflexivité, Proximité. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffrin, Seana Valentine. 2000. Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation. Philosophy & Public Affairs 29(3): 205–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zacka, Bernardo. 2017. When the State Meets the Streets: Public Service and Moral Agency. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank the editors and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments. For their support and illuminating feedback, I am also grateful to Thomas Christiano, Ben Cilwick, Daniel Dzah, Connor Kianpour, Jake Monaghan, Gregory Robson, Alexander Schaefer, David Schmidtz, Vlad Tarko, and Steve Wall. Finally, I would like to thank the students of my Philosopy of Law course at the University of San Diego for their brilliant comments, especially Damiera Cruz, Lily Hogan, and Lex Padilla.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario I. Juarez-Garcia.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no potential conflicts of interest.

Human or Animal Rights

No research involving human participants and/or animals was carried out for this work.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Juarez-Garcia, M.I. Official Disobedience: Bureaucrats & Unjust Laws. Criminal Law, Philosophy (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-023-09689-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-023-09689-1

Keywords