Advertisement

Criminal Law and Philosophy

, Volume 5, Issue 2, pp 115–146 | Cite as

Non-Tracing Cases of Culpable Ignorance

  • Holly M. Smith
Original Paper

Abstract

Recent writers on negligence and culpable ignorance have argued that there are two kinds of culpable ignorance: tracing cases, in which the agent’s ignorance traces back to some culpable act or omission of hers in the past that led to the current act, which therefore arguably inherits the culpability of that earlier failure; and non-tracing cases, in which there is no such earlier failure, so the agent’s current state of ignorance must be culpable in its own right. An unusual but intriguing justification for blaming agents in non-tracing cases is provided by Attributionism, which holds that we are as blameworthy for our non-voluntary emotional reactions, spontaneous attitudes, and the ensuing patterns of awareness as we are for our voluntary actions. The Attributionist explanation for why some non-tracing cases involve culpability is an appealing one, even though it has limited scope. After providing a deeper account of why we should take the Attributionist position seriously, I use recent psychological research to argue for a new account of the conditions under which agents are culpable for straightforward instances of blameworthy acts. That account is extended to blameworthiness for non-voluntary responses. I conclude that even when the agent’s failure to notice arises from a nonvoluntary objectionable attitude, very few such cases are ones in which Attributionism implies that the agent is blameworthy for her act.

Keywords

Attributionism Blame Blameworthiness Culpability Culpable ignorance Defenses Excuses Ignorance of fact Moral responsibility Negligence Non-tracing Volitionism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

For comments on earlier versions of this paper I am grateful to Alvin Goldman, Karen Shanton, discussants at Union College, and especially Douglas Husak and Kenneth Simons.

References

  1. Adams, R. (1985). Involuntary sins. The Philosophical Review, XCIV(1), 3–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bargh, J. A. (2005). Bypassing the will: Toward demystifying the nonconscious control of social behavior. In R. R. Hassin, J. S. Uleman, & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 37–60). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Carey, B. (2010, July 5). The benefits of blowing your top. The New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/07/06/health/06mind.html?ref=benedict_carey. Accessed 12 November 2010.
  5. Chartrand, T. J., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). The chameleon effect: The perception-behavior link and social interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 893–910.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Choi, Y. S., Gray, H. M., & Ambady, N. (2005). The glimpsed world: unintended communication and unintended perception. In R. R. Hassin, J. S. Uleman, & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 309–333). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Dijksterhuis, A., & Bargh, J. A. (2001). The perception-behavior expressway: Automatic effects of social perception on social behavior. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances of experimental social psychology (Vol. 33, pp. 1–40). San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  8. Evans, J. S. B. T., & Frankish, K. (Eds.). (2009). In two minds: Dual processes and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), The importance of what we care about (pp. 8–94). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. The Journal of Philosophy CV(10), 634–663.Google Scholar
  11. Glaser, J., & Kihlstrom, J. K. (2005). Compensatory automaticity: Unconscious volition is not an oxymoron. In R. R. Hassin, J. S. Uleman, & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 171–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Goldman, A. I. (1970). A theory of human action. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc.Google Scholar
  13. Hassin, R. R., Uleman, J. S., & Bargh, J. (Eds.). (2005). The new unconscious. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Hieronymi, P. (2008). Responsibility for believing. Synthese, 161, 357–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Jones, V. (2010, July 25). Shirley Sherrod and me. The New York Times Week in Review, p. WK10.Google Scholar
  16. King, M. (2009). The problem with negligence. Social Theory and Practice, 35(4), 577–595.Google Scholar
  17. Levy, N. (2005). The good, the bad, and the blameworthy. Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy, 1(2), 2–16.Google Scholar
  18. Liberman P. & Pizarro, D. (2010, October 24). All politics is olfactory. The New York Times Online http://www.nytimes.com/2010/10/24/opinion/24pizarro.html?scp=1&sq=All%20politics%20is%20olfactory&st=Search. Accessed November 12, 2010.
  19. Moore, M. S. & Hurd, H. M. (2011). Punishing the awkward, the stupid, the weak, and the selfish: The culpability of negligence. Criminal Law and Philosophy, this volume.Google Scholar
  20. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Sher, G. (2009). Who knew?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  23. Smith, A. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115, 236–271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Smith, A. (2008). Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies, 138(3), 367–392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Smith, H. (1983). Culpable ignorance. The Philosophical Review XCII(4), 543–571.Google Scholar
  26. Smith, H. (1991). Varieties of moral worth and moral credit. Ethics, 101, 279–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Smith, H. (2011, February) The ‘Prospective View’ of obligation. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy. http://www.jesp.org.
  28. Taylor, R. (1970). Good and evil. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
  29. The American Law Institute. (1985). Model penal code.Google Scholar
  30. Uhlmann, E. L., Pizzaro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2008). Varieties of social cognition. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 38(3), 293–322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Wallace, J. R. (1996). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Watson, G. (2004). Two faces of responsibility. In G. Watson (Ed.), Agency and responsibility (pp. 260–288). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Weingarten, G. (2009, March 8). Fatal distraction: Forgetting a child in the backseat of a car is a horrifying mistake. Is it a crime? Washington Post. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2009/02/27/AR2009022701549.html. Accessed November 12, 1020.
  34. Williams, B. (1973). Morality and the emotions. In B. Williams (Ed.), Problems of the self (pp. 207–229). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Witmer, J. (2010a). Sisters in arms: A father remembers. Homegrown New Berlin, WI: Library Lane Publishing.Google Scholar
  36. Witmer, J. (2010b, August 13). Interview on all things considered. National Public Radio Station WNYC.Google Scholar
  37. Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Zimmerman, M. J. (2008). Living with uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentRutgers UniversityNew BrunswickUSA

Personalised recommendations