NanoEthics

, Volume 6, Issue 3, pp 215–229 | Cite as

Visions and Ethics in Current Discourse on Human Enhancement

  • Arianna Ferrari
  • Christopher Coenen
  • Armin Grunwald
Original Paper

Abstract

Since it is now broadly acknowledged that ethics should receive early consideration in discourse on emerging technologies, ethical debates tend to flourish even while new fields of technology are still in their infancy. Such debates often liberally mix existing applications with technologies in the pipeline and far-reaching visions. This paper analyses the problems associated with this use of ethics as “preparatory” research, taking discourse on human enhancement in general and on pharmaceutical cognitive enhancement in particular as an example. The paper will outline and discuss the gap between the scientific and technological state of the art and the ethical debates, pointing out epistemic problems in this context. Furthermore, it will discuss the future role of genuine ethical reflection in discourse on human enhancement, arguing also that such discourse needs to include a technology assessment—in the broad sense of the term—which encompasses, inter alia, anthropological perspectives and aspects of social theory.

Keywords

Visions Human enhancement Ethics Speculative ethics Pharmaceutical cognitive enhancement 

References

  1. 1.
    Advokat C (2010) What are the cognitive effects of stimulant medications? Emphasis on adults with attention deficit/hyperactivity disorder (ADHD). Neurosci Biobehav Rev 34:1256–1266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Baranski JV, Pigeau R, Dinich P, Jacobs I (2004) Effects of modafinil on cognitive and meta-cognitive performance. Hum Psychopharmacol 19(5):323–332Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Bechmann G (1993) Ethische Grenzen der Technik oder technische Grenzen der Ethik? Geschichte und Gegenwart, 12:213–225Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Béland JP et al (2011) The social and ethical acceptability of NBICs for purposes of human enhancement: why does the debate remain mired in impasse? NanoEthics 5(3):295–307CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Boenink M, Swierstra T, Stemerding D (2010) Anticipating the interaction between technology and morality: a scenario study of experimenting with humans in bionanotechnology. Stud Ethics Law Technol 4(2)Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Bogle KE, Smith BH (2009) Illicit methylphenidate use: a review of prevalence, availability, pharmacology, and consequences. Curr Drug Abuse Rev 2(2):157–176CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Bostrom N, Sandberg A (2009) Cognitive enhancement: methods, ethics, regulatory challenges. Sci Eng Ethics 15(3):311–341Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Boyle J et al (2011) Acute sleep deprivation: the effects of the AMPAKINE compound CX717 on human cognitive performance, alertness and recovery sleep. J Psychopharmacol 26(8):1047–1057CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Brey PAE (2012) Anticipatory ethics for emerging technologies. NanoEthics 6(1):1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Caldera EO (2008) Cognitive enhancement and theories of justice: contemplating the malleability of nature and self. J Evol Technol 18(01), http://jetpress.org/v18/caldera.htm
  11. 11.
    Clatworthy PL et al (2009) Dopamine release in dissociable striatal subregions predicts the different effects of oral methylphenidate on reversal learning and spatial working memory. J Neurosci 29:4690–4696CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Coenen C (2010) Deliberating visions: the case of human enhancement in the discourse on nanotechnology and convergence. In: Kaiser M et al (eds) Governing future technologies. Nanotechnology and the rise of an assessment regime. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 73–88Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Coenen C (2008) Von der Leistungs- zur Leistungssteigerungsgesellschaft? TAB-Brief 33. Büro für Technikfolgen-Abschätzung, Berlin, pp 21–27Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Coenen C, Schuijff M, Smits M, Klaassen P, Hennen L, Rader M, Wolbring G (2009) Human enhancement. Brussels: European Parliament (http://www.itas.fzk.de/deu/lit/2009/coua09a.pdf)
  15. 15.
    Collingridge D (1980) The social control of technology, LondonGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Cooper AC (1999) The slippey slope and technological determinism. Princet J Bioeth 2(1):64–76Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Elliott C (1998) What’s wrong with enhancement technologies? CHIPS Public Lecture, University of Minnesota, February 26, 1998, Center for Bioethics, University of Minnesota, http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~ucbtdag/bioethics/writings/Elliott.html
  18. 18.
    Farah M et al (2004) Neurocognitive enhancement: what can we do and what should we do? Nat Rev Neurosci 421–425Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Ferrari A (2012) Autonomie und Visionen in der Debatte um pharmakologisches Cognitive Enhancement (PCE). In: Beck S (ed) Gehört mein Körper noch mir? Strafgesetzgebung zur Verfügungsbefugnis über den eigenen Körper in den Lebenswissenschaften. Nomos Verlag (in press)Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Forlini C, Racine E (2010) Response. Bioeth Inq 7:383–386CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Fox RC, Swazey JP (2008) Observing bioethics. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Franke AG, Lieb K (2010) Pharmacological neuroenhancement and brain doping: chances and risks. Bundesgesundheitsblatt Gesundheitsforschung Gesundheitsschutz 53:853–859Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Franke AG et al (2011) Non-medical use of prescription stimulants and illicit use of stimulants for cognitive enhancement in pupils and students in Germany. Pharmacopsychiatry 44(2):60–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Franke AG, Lieb K, Hildt E (2012) What users think about the differences between caffeine and illicit/prescription stimulants for cognitive enhancement. PLoS ONE 7(6):e40047. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0040047
  25. 25.
    Galert T et al (2009) Das optimierte Gehirn, In: Gehirn und Geist 11, http://zeus.zeit.de/wissen/2009-10/memorandum-gehirn-geist.pdf
  26. 26.
    Goordjin B (2005) Nanoethics: from Utopian dreams and apocalyptic nightmares towards a more balanced view. Sci Eng Ethics 11(4):521–533CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Greely H et al (2008) Towards responsible use of cognitive-enhancing drugs by the healthy. Nature 456:702–705CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Grunwald A (2010) From speculative nanoethics to explorative philosophy of nanotechnology. NanoEthics 4:91–101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 29.
    Grunwald A (2006) Nanotechnologie als Chiffre der Zukunft. In: Nordmann A, Schummer J, Schwarz A (eds) Nanotechnologien im Kontext. Berlin, pp 49–80Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Grunwald A (2011) Energy futures: diversity and the need for assessment. Futures 43(8):820–830CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Grunwald A (2012) Responsible Nano(bio)technology. Philosophy and Ethics. Singapore (in press)Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Hansson SO (2006) Great uncertainty about small things. In: Schummer J, Baird D (eds) Nanotechnology challenges—implications for philosophy, ethics and society. Singapur et al., pp 315–325Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Hays S, Miller CA, Cobb MD (2011) Public attitudes towards nanotechnology-enabled cognitive enhancement in the United States (Ch. 3). In: Hays S, Robert J, Miller C, Bennett I (eds) The yearbook of nanotechnology: nanotechnology, the brain, and the future, volume III. Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  34. 34.
    Jasanoff S, Kim S-H (2009) Containing the atom: sociotechnical imaginaries and nuclear power in the United States and South Korea. Minerva 47:119–146CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 35.
    Johnston LD et al (2005) Monitoring the future: national survey results on drug use, 1975-2004. Volume I: secondary school students. Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration’s National Clearinghouse for Alcohol and Drug Information, U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Rockville, MD, http://eric.ed.gov/ERICWebPortal/search/detailmini.jsp?_nfpb=true&_&ERICExtSearch_SearchValue_0=ED489468&ERICExtSearch_SearchType_0=no&accno=ED489468
  36. 36.
    Jonas H (1979) Das Prinzip Verantwortung: Versuch einer Ethik für die technologische Zivilisation, Frankfurt a. M, Suhrkamp VerlagGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Jones R, Morris K, Nutt D (2007) Cognition Enhancers, Review commissioned by the Parlamentary Office of Science and Technology, www.bis.gov.uk/assets/bispartners/...science/cognition-enhancers.pdf
  38. 38.
    Karafyllis NC (2009) Facts or fiction? A critique on vision assessment as a tool for technology assessment. In: Sollie P, Düwell M (eds) Evaluating new technologies, The International Library of Ethics, Law and Technology 3, II:93–117Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Khushf G (2005) The use of emergent technologies for enhancing human performance: are we prepared to address the ethical and political issues? Public Policy & Practice 4/2, n.p.; http://www.ipspr.sc.edu/ejournal/Archives0805.asp
  40. 40.
    Killgore WDS et al (2009) Sustaining executive functions during sleep deprivation: a comparison of caffeine, dextroamphetamine, and modafinil. Sleep 32(2):205–216Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Lieb K (2010) Hirndoping: Warum wir nicht alles schlucken solllten, Artemis & WinklerGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Liebert W, Schmidt J (2010) Towards a prospective technology assessment. Challenges for technology assessment in the age of technoscience. Poiesis & Praxis 7(1-2):99–116Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    Looby A, Earleywine M (2011) Expectation to receive methylphenidate enhances subjective arousal but not cognitive performance. Exp Clin Psychopharmacol 19(6):433–444CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. 44.
    Lucivero F et al (2011) Assessing expectations: towards a toolbox for an ethics of emerging technologies. NanoEthics 5(2):129–141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 45.
    Lynch G et al (2011) The likelihood of cognitive enhancement. Pharmacol Biochem Behav 99(2):116–129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 46.
    Maher B et al (2008) Pool results: look who’s doping. Nature 452:674–675CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. 47.
    Martin PA et al (2011) Pharmaceutical cognitive enhancement: interrogating the ethics, adressing the issues. In: Segev I, Markram H (eds) Augmenting cognition. Epfl Press, ItalyGoogle Scholar
  48. 48.
    Nadler R, Reiner PB (2010) A call for data to inform discussion on cognitive enhancement. BioSocieties 5(4):481–482CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. 49.
    Nadler R, Reiner PB (2011) Prototypes or pragmatics? The open question of public attitudes toward enhancement. AJOB Neurosci 2(2):49f–50fCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. 50.
  51. 51.
    Nordmann A (2007) If and then: a critique of speculative nanoethics. NanoEthics 1:31–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. 52.
    Nordmann A, Rip A (2009) Mind the gap revisited. Nat Nanotechnol 4:273–274CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. 53.
    Nordmann A (2010) A forensics of wishing: technology assessment in the age of technoscience. Poiesis and Praxis 7(1–2):5–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. 54.
    Outram SM (2011) Ethical considerations in the framing of the cognitive enhancement debate. Neuroethics 5(2):173–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. 55.
    Outram SM (2010) The use of methylphenidate among students: the future of enhancement? J Med Ethics 36:198–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. 56.
    Palm E, Hansson SO (2006) The case for ethical technology assessment (eTA). Technol Forecast Soc Chang 73:543–558CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. 57.
    Patenaude J et al (2011) Moral arguments in the debate over nanotechnologies: are we talking past each other? NanoEthics 5(3):285–293CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. 58.
    Quednow B (2011) Ethics of neuroenhancement: a phantom debate. BioSocieties 5(1):153–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. 59.
    Quednow B (2010) Neurophysiologie des Neuro-enhancements: Möglichkeiten und Grenzen, Suchtmagazin 2/2010:19–26, http://www.suchtmagazin.ch/tl_files/templates/Suchtmagazin/user_upload/texte_old/text2-10.pdf
  60. 60.
    Racine E, Forlini C (2010) Cognitive enhancement, lifestyle choice or misuse of prescription drugs? Ethics blind spots in current debates. Neuroethics 3(1):1–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. 61.
    Randall DC, Shneerson JM, File SE (2005) Cognitive effects of modafinil in student volunteers may depend on IQ. Pharmacol Biochem Behav 82:133–139Google Scholar
  62. 62.
    Rehmann-Sutter C, Leach Scully J (2010) Which ethics for (of) the nanotechnologies? In: Kaiser M et al (eds) Governing future technologies. Nanotechnology and the rise of an assessment regime. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 233–252Google Scholar
  63. 63.
    Repantis D et al (2010) Modafinil and methylphenidate for neuroenhancement in healthy individuals: a systematic review. Pharmacol Res 62(3):187–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. 64.
    Repantis D et al (2010) Acetylcholinesterase inhibitors and memantine for neuroenhancement in healthy individuals: a systematic review. Pharmacol Res 61(6):473–481CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. 65.
    Rip A, Kemp R (1998) Technological change. In: Rayne S, Malone L (eds) Human choice and climate change, vol 2 resources and technology. Batelle Press, Washington, pp 327–399Google Scholar
  66. 66.
    Rip A, Te Kulve H (2008) Constructive technology assessment and socio-technical scenarios. In: Fisher E, Selin C, Wetmore JM (eds) The yearbook of nanotechnology in society, vol 1: presenting futures. Springer, Berlin, pp 49–70Google Scholar
  67. 67.
    Roache R (2008) Ethics, speculation, and values. NanoEthics 2:317–327CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. 68.
    Sahakian B, Morein-Zhamir S (2007) Professor’s little helper. Nature 450:1157–1159CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. 69.
    Sandel M (2007) The case against perfection. Ethics in the age of genetic engineering, Belknap Press of Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
  70. 70.
    Sauter A, Gerlinger K (2011) Pharmakologische Interventionen zur Leistungssteigerung als gesellschaftliche Herausforderung, TAB-Arbeitsbericht Nr. 143., TAB, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  71. 71.
    Savulescu J, Bostrom N (2008) Human enhancement ethics: the state of the debate. In: Savulescu J, Bostrom N (eds) Human enhancement. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–22Google Scholar
  72. 72.
    Schleim S (2010) Cognitive enhancement—Sechs Gründe dagegen. In: Fink H, Rosenzweig R (ed) Künstliche Sinne, gedoptes Gehirn, pp. 179–207Google Scholar
  73. 73.
    Selin C (2007) Expectations and the emergence of nanotechnology. Sci Technol Hum Values 32(2):196–220CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. 74.
    Selin C (2011) Negotiating plausibility: intervening in the future of nanotechnology. Sci Eng Ethics 17(4):723–737CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. 75.
    Silber BY et al (2006) The acute effects of d-amphetamine and methamphetamine on attention and psychomotor performance. Psychopharmacology 187:154–169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. 76.
    Smith ME, Farah M (2011) Are prescription stimulants “smart pills”? The epidemiology and cognitive neuroscience of prescription stimulant use by normal healthy individuals, Psychological Bulletin© 2011 American Psychological Association 2011, 000-000 0033-2909/11/$12.00. doi:10.1037/a0023825
  77. 77.
    Stahl B (2011) IT for a better future: how to integrate ethics, politics and innovation. J Inform Comm Ethics Soc 9(3):140–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. 78.
    Teter CJ et al (2006) Illicit use of specific prescription stimulants among college students: prevalence, motives, and routes of administration. Pharmacotherapy 26(10):1501–1510CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. 79.
    Van der Plas A, Smits M, Wehrmann C (2010) Beyond speculative robot ethics: a vision assessment study on the future of the robotic caretaker. Account Res Policies Qual Assur 17(6):299–315Google Scholar
  80. 80.
    Williams R (2006) Compressed foresight and narrative bias: pitfalls in assessing high technology futures. Sci Cult 15(4):327–348CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. 81.
    Wolbring G (2008) Why NBIC? Why human performance enhancement? Eur J Soc Sci Res 21(S):25–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  • Arianna Ferrari
    • 1
  • Christopher Coenen
    • 1
  • Armin Grunwald
    • 1
  1. 1.Karlsruhe Institute of Technology (KIT)Institute for Technology Assessment and System Analysis (ITAS)KarlsruheGermany

Personalised recommendations