Skip to main content
Log in

Spinoza on Essence Constitution

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue that, against what is commonly believed, Spinoza’s use of the relation of constitution to characterize the relation between attributes and the essence of a substance does not indicate that, for him, there must be a numerical identity between each attribute and the essence constituted by that attribute. To do this, I follow a twofold strategy. First, I contend that the claim that because in Spinoza’s time constitution was understood as a one- to-one relation is mistaken: the main logicians of Spinoza’s time, all Cartesian philosophers, believe that the constitution of an essence can be a many-to-one relation. I show that Spinoza can both accept that constitution is a many-one relation and share Descartes’ understanding of this relation. Second, I defend the claim that Spinoza’s use of constitution in the Ethics is consistent with these logicians’ account of constitution. In particular, I focus on Spinoza’s inclusion of the intellect in the definition of attribute and his definition of God.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, all Della Rocca (2002), Melamed (2013), Lin (2019), and Shein (2009) seem to accept this claim. Other reasons for believing that attributes are numerically identical commonly discussed in Spinoza scholarship include: (1) Spinoza’s claim that attributes must be distinguished only by reason -e.g., Lin (2019) and Melamed (2017)-, (2) Spinoza’s use of the relation of expression in the Ethics -e.g., Della Rocca (2002) and Newlands (2018), and (3) the fact that positing the numerical identity of the attributes avoids the need of further explaining the unity of all attributes in one essence – e.g., Della Rocca (2008). Recently, Della Rocca (2019) has provided an innovative and insightful account of Spinoza’s view of number that can be regarded as a further reason for the view that attributes cannot be numerically distinct: (4) the claim that for Spinoza the notion of number cannot apply to attributes. I believe that each (1)-(4) deserves independent response by those believing that for Spinoza attributes are numerically distinct. However, my aim in this paper is limited to showing that the claim that attributes must be numerically identical because for Spinoza constitution is a one-one relation is mistaken. All my references to Spinoza’s works correspond to Curley’s translation (1984) -see reference list for abbreviations. All my citations of Descartes’s works correspond to Cottingham’s translation (1985).

  2. Gueroult (1968) and Smith (2014) are notable exceptions to this reading.

  3. Against this see Curley (1988). Curley believes that Spinoza’s rejection of (ii) is supported by his claim that attributes are what can be perceived by an infinite intellect as constituting an essence of substance rather than the essence of a substance. This reading is allowed by the Latin, which does not use articles. Thus, on this reading the number of essences of a substance is proportional to the number of the attributes of that substance. A similar view has been recently defended by Newlands (2019).

  4. Neither Clauberg (2007) or Arnauld and Nicole (1996) accept this view.

  5. For example, Burgersdijck (2011) and Heereboord (1654) do not recognize this possibility.

  6. Alan Donagan (1987) believes that the fact that this is how constitution was understood in Spinoza’s time is reflected in de Vries objection to the possibility of a substance having more than one numerically distinct attribute. In a letter to Spinoza (Ep.8), de Vries writes that “each substance has only one attribute, and if I had the idea of two attributes, I could rightly conclude that, where there are two different attributes, there are two different substances”. Note that de Vries seems to be following Descartes here: since each substance has only one attribute, wherever there are two attributes, there are two substances.

  7. As we have seen, Gueroult (1968) and Smith (2014) deny (i), whereas Curley (1988) denies (ii).

  8. It will later be clear that this account is, in a sense, similar to the Aristotelian understanding of essential attributes.

  9. For a detailed study of the main Dutch Cartesians of Spinoza’s time and their influence in his philosophy, see Douglas (2015). For an inventory of Spinoza’s Cartesian influences, see Van Bunge (2011).

  10. Both books were part of Spinoza’s library. The relation of constitution is more thoroughly developed in the latter book, which came to replace the first as the main logical textbook of its time and was published shortly after Spinoza abandoned the writing of the KV (late 1661 or early 1662) and before Spinoza completed the first draft of the Ethics (Verbeek 2015: 123-4).

References

Spinoza’s Works

  • Spinoza, B. (1984). The Collected Works of Spinoza, vol. 1. Translated and edited by Edwin Curley. Princeton: Princeton University Press. In citing from the Ethics, I use the following abbreviations: App Appendix, A Axiom, C Corollary, D Definition, Dem  Demonstration, Expl Explanation, P Proposition, S Scholium.

Other Sources

  • Arnauld, A., & Pierre N. (1996). Logic or the Art of Thinking. Trans by Jill Vance Buroker. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press

  • Van Bunge, W. (2011). The Bloomsbury Companion to Spinoza. Bloomsbury Companions. Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgersdijck, F. (2011). Monitio logica, or, An abstract and translation of Burgersdicius his logick by a gentleman. London: Printed for Ric. Cumberland ..., 1697; : Text Creation Partnership. http://name.umdl.umich.edu/A30233.0001.001.

  • Clauberg, J. (2007). Logique ancienne et nouvelle. Vrin.

  • Curley, E. (1988). Behind the geometrical method: A reading of Spinoza's Ethics. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Della Rocca, M. (2019). The elusiveness of the one and the many in Spinoza: Substance, attribute, and mode. In C. Ramond & J. Stetter (Eds.), Spinoza in 21st-century American and French philosophy: Metaphysics, philosophy of mind, moral and political philosophy. Bloomsbury Academic, Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Rocca, M. (2002). Spinoza's Substance Monism. In Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, Chapter 1. Oxford University Press.

  • Descartes, R. (1985). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Volume 1. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge University Press.

  • Donagan, A. (1987). Substance, Essence and Attribute in Spinoza: Ethics I. Humanities Working Chapter 122. California Institute of Technology.

  • Douglas, A. X. (2015). Spinoza and Dutch Cartesianism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gueroult, M. (1968). Spinoza I-Dieu. Aubier Philosophie. 

  • Heereboord, A.(1654). Adriani Heereboord, ... Philosophia Naturalis, Moralis, Rationalis. [Collegium Logicum].

  • Lin, M. (2019). Being and reason: An essay on Spinoza's metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

  • Melamed, Y. (2013). Spinoza's metaphysics: Substance and thought. Oxford University Press.

  • Newlands, S. (2018). Reconceiving Spinoza (First ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmaltz, T. (2020). The Metaphysics of the Material World: Suárez, Descartes, Spinoza. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shein, N. (2009). The False Dichotomy between Objective and Subjective Interpretations of Spinoza's Theory of Attributes. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17(3), 505–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2014). Spinoza, Gueroult, and Substance. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(3), 655–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, T. (2015). “Clauberg, Johannes (1622–1665).” Chapter. In L. Nolan (Ed.), The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon (pp. 123–124). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.053

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonio Salgado Borge.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Borge, A.S. Spinoza on Essence Constitution. Philosophia 50, 987–999 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00437-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00437-0

Keywords

Navigation