Skip to main content
Log in

The Frege-Geach Problem and Blackburn’s Expressivism

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Blackburn has outlined a formal account for moral expressivism, and we argued that the moral Frege-Geach problem can be solved formally by appending two rules for the boo-operator which are missing from his account. We then extended Blackburn’s formal account to generate a similar solution to the problem in modal context and showed that the validity of the modal argument can be preserved too in modal expressivism. However, the higher-order element endorsed by Blackburn does not seem necessary for solving the Frege-Geach problem. Nor is his extension from moral expressivism to modal expressivism tenable, since the latter violates its own ontological constraint. A general moral is drawn on the basis on three observations made in evaluating Blackburn’s expressivism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One of the earliest attempts was made by R. M. Hare (1970). His proposal is essentially compositional semantics for expressivist language, which sets the standard for subsequent proposals. In Schroeder (2008), which is among the most recent attempts, the core of solution is still compositional semantics.

  2. Our explanation of Blackburn’s higher-order approach is based mainly on his (1984: 195). The arrow sign ‘⇒’ first appears in Blackburn (1988: 508).

  3. Such attitude clash was characterized as logical inconsistency in Blackburn (1971, 1984). Later, Blackburn (1988: 510) characterized it as belief inconsistency. Mark van Roojen (1996) objected that no logical inconsistency was involved in Blackburn’s translation.

  4. Blackburn writes ‘If H ! p expresses the attitude of endorsing the goal p, ~H ! p then expresses its opposition: tolerating ~p or allowing it to be consistent with an ideal world. So, we can say that T ! A is substitutable for ~H ! A, and H ! A for ~T ! A.’ (1988: 511). Two notes are in order. First, the words ‘goal’ and ‘ideal world’ indicate that Blackburn’s logic is about norms. Second, if ‘~H ! p’ expresses the tolerance of ~p, i.e. ‘T ! ~p’, then what is substitutable for ‘T ! A’ is ‘~H ! ~A’, and what is substitutable for ‘H ! A’ is ‘~T ! ~A’. Schwartz and Hom (Schwartz and Hom 2014: 834) have the same reading as we have.

  5. This rule is based on Blackburn (1988: 508)‘s idea that ‘The contrary attitude B ! p would rule p out of any perfect world.’

  6. See Blackburn (1988: 512) for his reading of conditional in this logic.

  7. Ian G. McFetridge (1990: 145) testifies to the same reading of Blackburn’s account: ‘[Blackburn] is agnostic as to whether modal judgments have truth conditions in any substantive sense: whether in making them we are describing any further aspects of reality.’

  8. If ‘N!’ and ‘I!’ truly mirror ‘□’ and ‘~◇’, then the modal argument can be reformulated as ‘~ ◇ (2 > 3); □(~ ◇ (2 > 3) ⇒ ~ ◇ (2 > 4)); Therefore, ~ ◇ (2 > 4).’ Its validity can be proved easily in a normal modal logic whose accessibility relation is both symmetric and transitive.

  9. This transformation scheme is not fine-grained enough to handle the negation problem, which requires the expressivist logic to distinguish, say, ‘Smith believes that giving to charity is not required’ from ‘Smith does not believe that giving to charity is required’ and ‘Smith believes that not giving to charity is required.’ This problem is formally solvable, as Schroeder (2008), Silk (2015) and Schwartz and Hom (2014) show, though it will demand a substantial amendment to Blackburn’s logic.

  10. Blackburn’s higher-order approach is a customary target of criticism, for example Mark van Roojen (1996) argues that the higher-order account overgenerates valid arguments.

  11. Here we thank the anonymous reviewer for pointing out that being ontologically committed to possible worlds might not be problematic for someone who takes modal concepts to be irreducible.

References

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. New York: Dover Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1971). Moral realism. In J. Casey (Ed.), Morality and moral reasoning (pp. 101–124). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the word: Groundings in the philosophy of language. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1987). Morals and modals. In G. Macdonald & C. Wright (Eds.), Fact, science and morality (pp. 119–141). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1988). Attitudes and contents. Ethics, 98, 501–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1935). Philosophy and logical syntax. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2006). Negation for expressivists: A collection of problems with a suggestion for their solution. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 1, pp. 217–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2000). A priority as an evaluative notion. In P. Boghossian & C. Peacocke (Eds.), New essays on the a priori (pp. 117–149). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1960). Ascriptivism. Philosophical Review, 69, 221–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1965). Assertion. Philosophical Review, 74, 449–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1952). The language of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1970). Meaning and speech acts. The Philosophical Review, 79, 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1969). Deontic logic and its philosophical morals. In Models for modalities: Selected essays (pp. 184–214). Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. 1989. Philosophical Papers and Letters. Trans. L. E. Loemker. 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • McFetridge, I. (1990). Logical necessity: Some issues. In J. Haldane & R. Scruton (Eds.), Logical necessity and other essays (pp. 135–154). London: The Aristotelian Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1983). Does ‘probably’ modify sense? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 396–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2008). Being for: Evaluating the semantic program of Expressivism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J., & Hom, C. (2014). Why the negation problem is not a problem for expressivism. Noûs, 48, 824–845.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silk, A. (2015). How to be an ethical expressivist. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91, 47–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, C. L. (1937). The emotive meaning of ethical terms. Mind, 43, 14–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Roojen, M. (1996). Expressivism and irrationality. The Philosophical Review, 105, 311–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas, P. B. M. (2008). New foundations for imperative logic I: Logical connectives, consistency, and quantifiers. Noûs, 42, 529–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas, P. B. M. (2011). New foundations for imperative logic: Pure imperative inference. Mind, 120, 369–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas, P. B. M. (2016). New foundations for imperative logic III: A general definition of argument validity. Synthese, 193, 1703–1753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub, R. (2011). Logic for expressivists. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 601–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116, 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2012). Bayesian expressivism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112, 123–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chiu Yui Plato Tse.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hung, CH., Tse, C.Y.P. The Frege-Geach Problem and Blackburn’s Expressivism. Philosophia 48, 2021–2031 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00194-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00194-6

Keywords

Navigation