Skip to main content
Log in

Representationalism and the Intentionality of Moods

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It seems hard to comprehend how, during mood experience, the ‘inner’ meets the ‘outer’. The objective of this paper is to show that a currently popular attempt at providing a neat solution to that problem fails. The attempt comes under the heading of representationalism, according to which the phenomenal aspects of mood are exhausted by its representational content. I examine three accounts of intentionality developed within the representationalist camp, and I show that they incur phenomenological and metaphysical costs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. Ben-Ze'ev (2000) on the significance of change for emotional life.

  2. Searle (1983, 2), Dretske (1995, xv), Deonna and Teroni (2012, 4).

  3. De Sousa (1987), Goldie (2000), DeLancey (2006).

  4. Hatzimoysis (2003a)

  5. On the current debate over the nature and limits of privileged access see Hatzimoysis (2011) and Neta (2011).

  6. Rattcliffe (2010) includes a good survey of the relevant empirical and interpretative research.

  7. That is, also, one of the considerations that can be adduced in support of perceptual accounts of emotion; cf. Elgin (1996), Roberts (2003), Deonna (2006).

  8. Delancey (2006); cf. Solomon (1993, 71), Frijda (1994, 60), Prinz (2004, 182–188), Fish (2005).

  9. For approaches that adopt some version of that taxonomy see Griffiths (1997), Lormand (1985), Sizer (2000), Nussbaum (2001), and Price (2006). In my view, that approach is problematic not because the affective landscape is homogeneous, but because it is a taxonomy that locates the differences at the wrong level - sometimes differences between emotions are more pronounced than the difference between an emotion and its consequent mood.

  10. Cf. Crane’s subtle argumentation in (Crane 1998) and (Crane 2013).

  11. Kenny (1963), Tappolet (2000), Terroni (2007).

  12. For a balanced discussion of the representationalist movement see Siewert (1998), (Siewert 2012).

  13. The argument from transparency can be found in Harman (1990), developed in Tye (2002), elaborated by Byrne (2001). For the varieties of ontological dependency involved in supervenient claims see Hatzimoysis (2003b).

  14. De Sousa (2004), Deonna and Teroni (2012), 68–69).

  15. Kind (2014), 130).

  16. Kind’s line of argumentation at (2014, 130–131) appears to me to imply as much.

  17. For Solomon, moods “are about the whole of our world” (Solomon 1976, 173), while for Lyons moods are “aimed out at the world” (Lyons 1980, 104); cf. Annette Baier (1990, 14).

  18. For Solomon, moods are “indiscriminately about anything that comes our way, casting happy glows or somber shadows on every object and incident of our experience” (Solomon 1976, 173); Solomon’s proposal is in tune with theories which highlight the puzzling fact that moods appear to be directed at both nothing and everything; cf. Goldie (2000, 18), De Sousa (2010), and Sizer (2000, 747) and for discussion Kind (2014), 120).

  19. Mendelovic (2013) ( 2014).

  20. I used the simplest interpretation of the notion of ‘object’ to illustrate the problem, but the criticism applies whatever technical notion the representationalist might invoke. If by ‘object’ she means, for instance, an unqualified substratum, or a qualified substance, or a bearer of qualities, the point remains that something need not fall in those ontological categories to count as intentional object.

  21. Mendelovic (2013), ( 2014).

  22. I leave aside issues raised by haeccity: even if we were to admit such property in our ontology, it would not be of help to the current representationalist proposal, since it is a property bound, by definition, to some particular object.

  23. Mendelovic (2013), ( 2014).

References

  • Baier, A. (1990). What emotions are about. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Ze'ev, A. (2000). The subtlety of emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review, 110(2), 199–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2013). The objects of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1998). Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Contemporary issues in the philosophy of mind (pp. 136–157). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, R. (1987). The rationality of emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, R. (2004). Emotions: What I know, what I’d like to think I know, and what I’d like to think. In R. C. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking About Feeling, ed (pp. 61–75). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, Ronald (2010) ‘Emotion’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/emotion/.

  • DeLancey, C. (2006). Basic moods. Philosophical Psychology, 19, 527–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A. (2006). Emotion, perception and perspective. Dialectica, 60(1), 29–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2012). The emotions: A philosophical introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (1996). Considered Judgment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2005). Emotions, moods, and intentionality. In G. Forrai & G. Kampis (Eds.), Intentionality past and future (pp. 25–35). New York: Rodopi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. (1994). Varieties of affect: Emotions and episodes, moods and sentiments. In P. Ekman & R. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion (pp. 59–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2000). The emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are: The problem of psychological categories. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The Intrinsic Quality of Experience. In N. Block, O. J. Flanagan, & G. Güzeldere (Eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (pp. 663–675). Cambridge: Mass.: The MIT Press, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatzimoysis (2003a) ‘Emotional Feelings and Intentionalism’ in Philosophy and the Emotions, ed. by A. Hatzimoysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 105-112.

  • Hatzimoysis (2003b). ‘Analytical Descriptivism Revisited” Ratio, XV: 10-22.

  • Hatzimoysis (2011) ‘Introduction’ in Self-Knowledge, ed. by A. Hatzimoysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011: 1-8.

  • Kenny, A. (1963). Action, emotion and will. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2014). The case against representationalism about moods. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 113–134). London: Routlegde.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lormand, E. (1985). Towards a theory of moods. Philosophical Studies, 47, 385–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, W. (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici (2013) Intentionalism about moods. Thought 2: 126–136.

  • Mendelovici. (2014). Pure Intentionalism about moods and emotions. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 113–134). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R. (2011). The nature and reach of privileged access. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Self-Knowledge (Vol. 2011, pp. 9–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Price, C. (2006). Affect without object: Moods and objectless emotions. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 2, 49–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rattcliffe, M. (2010). The phenomenology of mood and the meaning of life. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of emotion (pp. 349–372). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions: An essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2012). Respecting appearances: A phenomenological approach to consciousness. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 48–69). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sizer, L. (2000). Towards a computational theory of mood. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 743–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1976). The passions. New York: Anchor Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1993). The passions: Emotions and the meaning of life. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2000). Emotions et Valeurs. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Terroni, F. (2007). Emotions and Formal Objects. Dialectica, 61(3), 395–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2002). Consciousness, Color and Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anthony Hatzimoysis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hatzimoysis, A. Representationalism and the Intentionality of Moods. Philosophia 45, 1515–1526 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9825-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9825-0

Keywords

Navigation