Skip to main content
Log in

Kant’s Solution to the Euthyphro Dilemma

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Are our actions morally good because we approve of them or are they good independently of our approval? Are we projecting moral values onto the world or do we detect values that are already there? For many these questions don’t state a real alternative but a secular variant of the Euthyphro dilemma: If our actions are good because we approve of them moral goodness appears to be arbitrary. If they are good independently of our approval, it is unclear how we come to know their moral quality and how moral knowledge can be motivating. None of these options seems attractive; the source of moral goodness unclear. Despite the growing literature on Kant’s moral epistemology and moral epistemology the question remains open what Kant’s answer to this apparent dilemma is. The Kantian view I attempt to lay out in this paper is supposed to dissolve the secular version of the Euthyphro dilemma. In responding to this dilemma we need to get clear about the source or the origin of our moral knowledge: Voluntary approval or mind-independent moral facts? Projectivism or detectivism? Construction or given? I believe that all these ways of articulating the problem turn out, on closer inspection, to be false alternatives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bagnoli, C. (2012). Morality as practical knowledge. Analytic Philosophy, 53, 61–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. (2013). Constructivism about practical knowledge. In C. Bagnoli (Ed.), Constructivism in ethics (pp. 153–182). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bojanowski, J. (2012). Is Kant a moral realist? Kant-Yearbook, 4, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (1996). Reason, humanity, and the moral law. In C. Korsgaard (Ed.), The sources of normativity (pp. 167–188). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Engstrom, S. (2009). The form of practical knowledge: A study of the categorical imperative. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Engstrom, S. (2013). Constructivism and practical knowledge. In C. Bagnoli (Ed.), Constructivism in ethics (pp. 153–182). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2006). Agency, shmagency: why normativity won't come from what is constitutive of agency. Philosophical Review, 115, 169–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2000). Morality of law and morality of freedom. in: Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 129–71.

  • Hussain, N. J. Z., & Shah, N. (2006). Misunderstanding metaethics: Korsgaard’s rejection of realism. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1 (pp. 265–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (2008). The constitution of agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M., et al. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2007). Objective and unconditioned value. Philosophical Review, 116, 157–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1996). Universality and the reflective self. In C. Korsgaard (Ed.), The sources of normativity (pp. 200–209). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1980). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. Journal of Philosophy, 77, 515–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönecker, D. (1999). Kant: Grundlegung III. Die Deduktion des kategorischen Imperativs. Freiburg: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, R. (2012). Understanding moral obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stratton-Lake, P. (2000). Kant, duty, and moral worth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Constructivism about reasons. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 3, 208–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (1998). Decision procedures, moral criteria, and the problem of relevant descriptions in Kant’s ethics. In B. S. Byrd, J. Hruschka, & J. C. Joerdan (Eds.), Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik (pp. 389–417). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (1999). Kant’s ethical thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (2008). Kantian ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very much indebted to Stefano Bacin, Carla Bagnoli, Patrick Kain, Pauline Kleingeld, Nico Naeve, Lara Ostaric, Fabienne Peter, Fred Rauscher, Joe Saunders, Dieter Schönecker, Irina Schumski, Oliver Sensen, Melissa Zinkin, and two anonymous referees for their comments on an earlier version of this paper. My work on this article was funded by the Netherlands Organization of Scientific Research (NWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jochen Bojanowski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bojanowski, J. Kant’s Solution to the Euthyphro Dilemma. Philosophia 44, 1209–1228 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9747-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9747-2

Keywords

Navigation