Skip to main content
Log in

A Pluralist Account of Knowledge as a Natural Kind

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In an attempt to address some long-standing issues of epistemology, Hilary Kornblith proposes that knowledge is a natural kind the identification of which is the unique responsibility of one particular science: cognitive ethology. As Kornblith sees it, the natural kind thus picked out is knowledge as construed by reliabilism. Yet the claim that cognitive ethology has this special role has not convinced all critics. The present article argues that knowledge plays a causal and explanatory role within many of our more fruitful current theories, diverging from the reliabilist conception even in disciplines that are closely related to cognitive ethology, and thus still dealing with knowledge as a natural as opposed to a social phenomenon, where special attention will be given to cognitive neuroscience. However, rather than discarding the natural kind approach altogether, it is argued that many of Kornblith’s insights can in fact be preserved within a framework that is both naturalist and pluralist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Siegel (2006) criticizes Kornblith for the role he ascribes to intuitions, which he views as question begging. I will grant that Siegel has a point here, although I think that Kornblith’s discussion can be seen as offering enough material to answer it. In my view, the issue Siegel raises hinges on whether or not one accepts the stance Kornblith promotes in his third claim. As I interpret Kornblith’s argument, he is aware that his line of reasoning demands an acceptance of naturalism. Made evident in his argument and possible to see in formulations such as: ‘From a naturalistic perspective, there are substantial advantages to looking outward at the phenomena under investigation rather than inward at our intuitions about them.’ (Kornblith 2002, p. 16, my italics). What Kornblith wants to do, as I understand him, is not to convince someone who is a firm non-naturalist that he or she has to accept that theoretical understanding trumps everyday intuitions, but rather give a plausible explanation of what role intuitions (can) fill in a naturalistic theory. So the question Kornblith discusses is that given a naturalistic stance, what role can intuitions play? The question begging that Siegel accuses Kornblith of seems to stem from an interpretation of Kornblith’s intentions that is not entirely correct or charitable.

  2. Kornblith does not elaborate on his version of naturalism, but rather takes it for granted.

  3. To put Kornblith’s ideas in context and perspective it might be illuminating to briefly mention that some more or less similar ideas, can be found in for example Maddy (2007) and van Fraassen (2002), who highlight that philosophy should adopt a scientific attitude – a stance. However, both Maddy’s and van Fraassen’s theories differ from Kornblith’s on crucial points.

  4. Both Kusch (2005) and Bermúdez (2006) question Kornblith’s argument against a division between human and animal knowledge, since they claim that even unreflective knowledge – in humans – have aspects of logical reasoning built into it. This should, according to Kusch and Bermúdez, be seen as a genuine difference, which Kornblith downplays or ignores. I will regard it to ultimately be an open issue, in that there are arguments both for and against a division. So both interpretations of cognitive ethology and the usage of knowledge regarding animals and humans are reasonable, and the issue is in itself hence not enough to pose any real problem for Kornblith’s theory.

  5. Bermúdez (2006) points out cases where cognitive ethologists disagree with Kornblith’s main tenets and about the possibility of using knowledge as a natural kind. I do not question Bermúdez in his argumentation and examples regarding other interpretations of how cognitive ethology should be viewed. But as concerning the previous point of anthropomorphism there is no general interpretation of the results from cognitive ethology that is totally conclusive and accepted by the majority of research, so I do not think that this is enough to pose a real threat to Kornblith’s theory.

  6. Kornblith actually writes that cognitive ethology is ‘One of the more fruitful areas […]’ (Kornblith 2002, p. 28, my italics).

  7. I will reconnect to this point below.

  8. An argument for the priority of cognitive ethology over cognitive neuroscience might be found in the thesis of multiple realizability, where cognitive ethology can be interpreted as better equipped to explain what knowledge is given its more functionalistic ultimate perspective. However, if the differences between humans and other animals are made salient, the same thesis can just as well be used against Kornblith’s earlier merging of human and animal knowledge, and instead be interpreted as pointing out the importance of species-specific differences.

  9. If this is not taken into account theoreticians risk talking past each other.

  10. A contrasting opinion and discussion can be found in for example Horvath (2016, pp. 175–176).

  11. Bermúdez mentions similar concerns, but sees the situation facing Kornblith’s theory as risking it being dubbed folk psychology rather than focusing on the possibility of an inclusive pluralism (Bermúdez 2006, p. 304).

References

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M., Dennett, D., Hacker, P., & Searle, J. (2007). Neuroscience and Philosophy: Brain, Mind, and Language. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2006). Knowledge, Naturalism, and Cognitive Ethology: Kornblith’s Knowledge and its Place in Nature. Philosophical Studies, 127, 299–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (ed.) (2009). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binder, J. R., & Desai, R. H. (2011). The Neurobiology of Semantic Memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(11), 527–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. and Tobin, E. (2012). ‘Natural Kinds’, In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/natural-kinds/>.

  • Bonjour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1988). The Indispensability of Internal Justification. Synthese, 74, 285–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M., & Churchland, P. S. (1998). On the Contrary: Critical Essays 1987–1997. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1996). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2009). The Free-Energy Principle: A Rough Guide to the Brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 293–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The Free-Energy Principle: A Unified Brain Theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R. B., & Mangun, G. R. (2002). Cognitive Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2005). Kornblith’s Naturalistic Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 403–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horst, S. (2011). Laws, Mind, and Free Will. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horst, S. (2016). Cognitive Pluralism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2016). Conceptual Analysis and Natural Kinds: The Case of Knowledge. Synthese, 193(1), 167–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1907 [1995]). Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. New York: Dover.

  • Kim, J. (1988). What is “Naturalized Epistemology”? Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 381–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klopfer, P. H. (2005). Animal Cognition and the New Anthropomorphism. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 18(3), 202–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Inductive Inference and Its Natural Ground: An Essay in Naturalistic Epistemology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its Place in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2005). Replies to Alvin Goldman, Martin Kusch and William Talbott. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 427–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2006). Reply to Bermúdez and BonJour. Philosophical Studies, 127, 337–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2012). On Reflection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (2005). Beliefs, Kinds and Rules: A Comment on Kornblith’s Knowledge and Its Place in Nature. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 411–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2007). Second Philosophy: A Naturalistic Method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, P., & Bateson, P. (2007). Measuring Behaviour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., & Borgida, E. (1975). Attribution and the psychology of prediction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32(5), 932–943.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2015). ‘Naturalism’, In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition). <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/naturalism/>

  • Patterson, K., Nestor, P. J., & Rogers, T. T. (2007). Where do You Know what you Know? The Representation of Semantic Knowledge in the Human Brain. Nature Review Neuroscience, 8, 976–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1877 [1955]). ‘The Fixation of Belief’, In J. Buchler (ed.), Philosophical Writings of Peirce (pp. 5–22). New York: Dover Publications, Inc.

  • Plotkin, H. C. (1993). Darwin Machines and the Nature of Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology Naturalized. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (pp. 69–90). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., Lepper, M. R., & Hubbard, M. (1975). Perseverance in self-perception and social perception: Biased attributional processes in the debriefing paradigm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32, 880–892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2016). ‘Naturalism in Epistemology’, In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition), forthcoming. <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/epistemology-naturalized/>

  • Scott-Phillips, T. C., Dickins, T. E., & West, S. A. (2011). Evolutionary Theory and the Ultimate-Proximate Distinction in the Human Behavioral Sciences. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6(1), 38–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. (1995). Here and Everywhere: Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. Annual Review of Sociology, 21, 289–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2013). Fundamentals of Comparative Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2006). Book Review: Hilary Kornblith, Knowledge and its Place in Nature. Philosophical Review, 115(2), 246–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. (1963). On Aims and Methods of Ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1985). Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology, 26(1), 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1971). Belief in the Law of Small Numbers. Psychological Bulletin, 76(2), 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). ‘Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases’, Science. New Series, 185(4157), 1124–1131.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (2002). The Empirical Stance. London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J. (2010). The Student’s Guide to Cognitive Neuroscience. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, C. D. L. (2007). What are Animals? Why Anthropomorphism is still not a Scientific Approach to Behavior. Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews, 2, 125–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yee, E., Chrysikou, E. G., & Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2014). Semantic Memory. In K. Ochsner & S. Kosslyn (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Neuroscience: Volume 1, Core Topics (pp. 353–374). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Erik J. Olsson for his guidance, helpful comments and for him being extremely charitable with his knowledge and time. Thanks to Johannes Persson, Shira Singer and my anonymous referees for comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Stephens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stephens, A. A Pluralist Account of Knowledge as a Natural Kind. Philosophia 44, 885–903 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9738-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9738-3

Keywords

Navigation