Advertisement

Philosophia

, Volume 44, Issue 1, pp 63–77 | Cite as

Is Objective Consequentialism Compatible with the Principle that “Ought” Implies “Can”?

  • Vuko Andrić
Article

Abstract

Some philosophers hold that objective consequentialism is false because it is incompatible with the principle that “ought” implies “can”. Roughly speaking, objective consequentialism is the doctrine that you always ought to do what will in fact have the best consequences. According to the principle that “ought” implies “can”, you have a moral obligation to do something only if you can do that thing. Frances Howard-Snyder has used an innovative thought experiment to argue that sometimes you cannot do what will in fact have the best consequences because you do not know what will in fact have the best consequences. Erik Carlson has raised two objections against Howard-Snyder’s argument. This paper examines Howard-Snyder’s argument as well as Carlson’s objections, arguing that Carlson’s objections do not go through but Howard-Snyder’s argument fails nonetheless. Moreover, this paper attempts to show that objective consequentialism and other objectivist moral theories are compatible with the principle that “ought” implies “can”. Finally, this paper analyses a special kind of inability: ignorance-induced inability.

Keywords

Objective consequentialism “Ought” implies “can” Ignorance-induced inability 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This paper has benefited from the comments of audiences in Saarbrücken and Konstanz. I am especially grateful for the help received from Christoph Fehige, Sebastian Köhler, and Attila Tanyi. Research on this paper has been funded by a project grant of the German Research Foundation (Grant number: TA 820/1-1).

References

  1. Andrić, V. (2015). Objective consequentialism and the rationales of “‘ought’ implies ‘can’”. Ratio. doi: 10.1111/rati.12108.
  2. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  3. Austin, J. L. (1956). Ifs and cans. Proceedings of the British Academy, 42, 107–132.Google Scholar
  4. Ayer, A. J. (1954). Freedom and necessity. In his Philosophical essays (pp. 271–284). London: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
  5. Baier, A. (1971). The search for basic actions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 8, 161–170.Google Scholar
  6. Carlson, E. (1999). The oughts and cans of objective consequentialism. Utilitas, 11(1), 91–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chisholm, R. M. (1964). The descriptive element in the concept of action. The Journal of Philosophy, 61, 613–624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Danto, A. C. (1963). What we can do. The Journal of Philosophy, 60, 435–445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons and causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 685–700.Google Scholar
  10. Fantl, J. (2012). Knowledge How. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/knowledge-how/.
  11. Fara, M. (2008). Masked abilities and compatibilism. Mind, 117, 843–865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Goldman, A. (1970). A theory of human action. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Howard-Snyder, F. (1997). The rejection of objective consequentialism. Utilitas, 9(2), 241–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Howard-Snyder, F. (1999). Response to Carlson and Qizilbash. Utilitas, 11(1), 106–111.Google Scholar
  15. Howard-Snyder, F. (2006). It’s the thought that counts. Utilitas, 17, 265–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hurley, S. (2000). Responsibility, reason, and irrelevant alternatives. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 28(3), 205–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kratzer, A. (1977). What ‘Must’ and ‘Can’ must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 337–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lehrer, K. (1976). ‘Can’ in theory and practice: A possible world analysis. In M. Brand & D. Walton (Eds.), Action theory (pp. 241–270). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Lewis, D. (1976). The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly, 13, 145–152.Google Scholar
  20. Maier, J. (2011). Abilities. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/abilities/.
  21. Mason, E. (2003). Consequentialism and the “Ought Implies Can” principle. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(4), 319–331.Google Scholar
  22. McCann, H. (1974). Volition and basic action. Philosophical Review, 83, 451–473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McCloskey, H. J. (1973). Utilitarianism: two difficulties. Philosophical Studies, 24, 62–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Miller, D. E. (2003). Actual-consequence act utilitarianism and the best possible humans. Ratio, 16(1), 49–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1966.Google Scholar
  26. Moore, E. (2007). Objective consequentialism, right actions, and good people. Philosophical Studies, 133, 83–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Qizilbash, M. (1999). The rejection of objective consequentialism: a comment. Utilitas, 11(1), 97–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Ripley, C. R. (1974). A theory of volition. American Philosophical Quarterly, 11, 141–147.Google Scholar
  29. Ryle, G. (1945). Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  31. Smith, M. (2003). Rational capacities, or: How to distinguish recklessness, weakness, and compulsion. In S. Stroud & C. Tappolet (Eds.), Weakness of will and pracical irrationality (pp. 17–38). Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Stanley, J. (2011). Knowing (How). Noûs, 45, 207–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Vihvelin, K. (2004). Free will demystified: a dispositionalist account. Philosophical Topics, 32, 427–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Wiland, E. (2005). Monkeys, typewriters, and objective consequentialism. Ratio, 18, 352–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of MannheimMannheimGermany

Personalised recommendations