Skip to main content
Log in

The Manipulation Argument, At the Very Least, Undermines Classical Compatibilism

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The compatibility of determinism and the ability to do otherwise has been implicitly assumed by many to be irrelevant to the viability of compatibilist responses to the manipulation argument for incompatibilism. I argue that this assumption is mistaken. The manipulation argument may be unsound. But even so, the manipulation argument, at the very least, undermines classical compatibilism, the view that free will requires the ability to do otherwise, and having that ability is compatible with determinism. This is because classical compatibilism, in conjunction with any type of reply to the manipulation argument, has counterintuitive implications. In order to avoid such implications, we need not hold that determinism is incompatible with moral responsibility. But we must hold that determinism is incompatible with the ability to do otherwise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a defense of classical compatibilism, see Saunders (1968), Lehrer (1976), Horgan (1979), Lewis (1981), Campbell (1997), Smith (2003), Fara (2008), Perry (2008), Kapitan (2011), Berofsky (2012), and Vihvelin (2013). Wolf (1990) and Nelkin (2011) do not hold that free will requires the ability to do otherwise. But they do hold that an agent is blameworthy for what she has done only if she could have done otherwise, and, crucially, having the ability to do otherwise is compatible with determinism. So Wolf and Nelkin are likewise subject to the challenge of this paper.

  2. For a defense of source compatibilism, see Frankfurt (1971), Watson (1975), Wallace (1994), McKenna (2005), and Sartorio (2011). Fischer and Ravizza (1998) who are semi-compatibilists similarly reject PAP and maintain that determinism is compatible with moral responsibility.

  3. As will become evident, I largely ignore Cases 2 and 3, and instead focus on comparing Case 1 with Case 4. The reason why I still focus on Pereboom’s argument rather than, e.g., Mele’s (2006) manipulation argument which only compares two cases is that the kind of direct manipulation present in Case 1 better serves my aim of drawing out certain implications from classical compatibilism.

  4. Some of these conditions include, but are not limited to, having the appropriate set of higher-order desires (Frankfurt 1971), being reasons-responsive (Fischer and Ravizza 1998), having the ability to regulate one’s actions by moral reasons (Wallace 1994), and having the ability to develop one’s moral character over time (Mele 1995; Haji 1998).

  5. Throughout the paper, I ignore the issue of satisfying epistemic conditions for responsibility since such conditions cut across the free will debate.

  6. All references to Case 1 and the FCMA henceforth are references to the new Case 1 and the new FCMA unless explicitly noted otherwise.

  7. For the purposes of this paper, I understand a historical condition for responsibility to include what I will call both a positive-historical condition and a negative-historical condition. A positive-historical condition concerns having a certain history. By contrast, a negative-historical condition concerns merely not having a certain kind of defective history (for further discussion, see e.g., McKenna (2012), Haji (2013), and Mele (2013)). This distinction is irrelevant to my argument below. For, I will be concerned with extrinsic differences between Plum1 and Plum4 which include (but are not necessarily limited to) both positive-historical conditions and negative-historical conditions for responsibility.

  8. This sort of consideration seems to have been largely overlooked in the literature.

  9. Smith (2003) and Fara (2008) are also so-called new dispositionalists.

  10. LCA-PROP-ABILITY draws its resources from the work of Lewis (1997) and Manley and Wasserman (2008).

  11. Notice that I am not committed to the claim that the ability to do otherwise is identical to the wide ability to do otherwise.

  12. A disposition (which, according to Vihvelin, is what an ability reduces to) is finkish when there is something that would remove the disposition precisely under conditions in which the disposition would ordinarily be manifested. A masked disposition is one in which, under conditions in which it would ordinarily be manifested, the disposition fails to be manifested without the disposition being removed.

  13. In order for LCA-PROP-ABILITY to apply to mental actions such as Plum’s decision to kill White, I am charitably assuming that it makes sense to try to decide to do something, and that there is a way around objections embodied by Lehrer’s (1968) red candy case. See Clarke (2009: 328–329) and Vihvelin (2013: 196–208).

  14. Perhaps a compatibilist can construct an alternative account of abilities whereby it is objectionable to stipulate that Plum1 and Plum4 are intrinsic duplicates of one another in all relevant respects and yet only Plum1 is being manipulated. However, unless such an alternative account of abilities is offered, I contend that such a stipulation about Cases 14 remains unproblematic.

  15. The SLCC theorist who accepts (i) and PAP would presumably say that Plum1 is not blameworthy for deciding to kill White at least partly because Plum1 was not able to do other than decide to kill White.

  16. Perhaps we lack ultimate ‘heaven and hell’ responsibility for our actions given that we are not causa sui. As Clarke (2005: 20–3) notes, however, it does not follow that we lack a weaker form of basic desert responsibility.

  17. One difference between Plum1 and the manager is that Plum1 is unaware of the manipulation, whereas the manager is, we may suppose, aware of the fact that the employee influenced the manager’s action of insulting the employee. But this difference is surely irrelevant. For, I know of no one who thinks that we must be aware of all of the factors that are influencing our action in order to be responsible for that action. Moreover, such a condition on responsibility would render virtually everyone blameless for their actions since virtually no one is aware of all of the factors that influence their actions.

  18. I understand the kind of manipulation in Case 1 to be direct, whereas the kind of manipulation in Case 2 (being programmed at the beginning of one’s life) fails to be direct.

  19. The libertarian would of course dispute the claim that Jones φ-s on her own if Jones’ φ-ing is causally determined by factors beyond her control. But here we are interested in what classical compatibilists such as Vihvelin say about traditional deterministic FSCs.

  20. Although Vihvelin does not explicitly say that Jones has the wide ability to do otherwise in a deterministic FSC in which Black doesn’t intervene but employs the Preemptor method, this is, I think, the correct and charitable interpretation of Vihvelin’s position given her use of an analogy of a coin toss in the context of Jones’ abilities in a deterministic FSC. More specifically, Vihvelin (2013: 104) says that a coin which comes up heads could have come up tails in light of not only the coin’s intrinsic properties, but also given “facts about its [the coin’s] environment”, i.e., given the coin’s opportunity to come up tails.

  21. Vihvelin holds that a deterministic FSC in which Black (who does not actually intervene) employs the Bodyguard method does not refute PAP even though Jones who φ-s does not retain the wide ability to ~φ but only retains the wide ability to, say, try to ~φ. Consider what Vihvelin’s (2013: 101) says:

    Insofar as Black is a Bodyguard […] he succeeds in depriving Jones of the alternative required for freedom of action, but he necessarily fails to deprive Jones of the alternatives required for freedom of will. And, of course, it is freedom of will that is the classical locus of moral responsibility.

    I understand Vihvelin’s remarks here not to concern the distinction between having a narrow ability to φ and a having wide ability to φ. Instead, I understand these remarks to concern the distinction between the performance of an overt bodily movement and the mere performance of a mental action. Applying Vihvelin’s remarks to the FCMA is complicated by the fact that the kind of action Plum performs is a decision—a mental action. Still, let’s continue to assume the coherence of trying to perform a decision. Now, suppose Vihvelin were to hold (as she very well may) that in order for Plum to be responsible for deciding to kill White, Plum only needs the wide ability to try to decide to kill White. Might Vihvelin avoid being committed to (C) even if, as a proponent of PAP, she were to endorse a hard-line reply? In other words, can Vihvelin commit to HLLC and (iii) without being committed to (C)? No. Instead of focusing on Plum1’s decision, we can simply shift our attention to Plum1’s attempt to make his decision. If Plum1 is responsible for his attempt to make his decision, and PAP is true, then Plum1 could have refrained from trying to make his decision, despite the fact that Plum1’s attempt to make his decision was the result of the direct manipulation of the neuroscientists.

    What if Vihvelin were to accept a hard-line reply, reject PAP as I understand the principle, and hold instead that an agent is responsible for what she has done only if she has the narrow (but not the wide) ability to do otherwise, or at least has the narrow (but not the wide) ability to try to do otherwise? If Vihvelin went this route, she would be subject to the second horn of my dilemma for the HLLC theorist which I will discuss shortly. Moreover, going this route seems to have the implausible implication that in the airplane scenario discussed in section 2, Jacqueline du Pré can be (non-derivatively) morally responsible for not playing the cello.

  22. Among the very few philosophers that have explicitly considered the relationship between classical compatibilism and the manipulation argument, Berofsky (2006: 435–9) claims that it is question-begging against the classical compatibilist to assume that an agent cannot do otherwise in the case of manipulation. My response is threefold. First, classical compatibilism does not by itself entail (C). So, to say that (C) is implausible does not amount to saying that classical compatibilism is implausible. Rather, the point of highlighting (C)’s implausibility is to show that the conjunction of HLCC and PAP is implausible. Second, as already noted, in light of what classical compatibilists such as Vihvelin seem to implicitly hold regarding Actual Intervention, there is indeed internal pressure upon such classical compatibilists to reject (C). Third, even if my case against (C) won’t convince a classical compatibilist, a group of agnostics about classical compatibilism would arguably be inclined to reject (C). This in turn should count as a cost to those who accept HLCC and PAP. In other words, my attack on (C) is not a so-called philosophical failure. For more on what does and does not constitute a philosophical failure, see Fischer and Tognazzini (2007).

References

  • Baker, L. R. (2006). Moral responsibility without libertarianism. Noûs, 40, 307–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berofsky, B. (2006). Global control and freedom. Philosophical Studies, 131, 419–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berofsky, B. (2012). Nature’s challenge to free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1997). A compatibilist theory of alternative possibilities. Philosophical Studies, 88, 319–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2005). On an argument for the impossibility of moral responsibility. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 13–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2009). Dispositions, abilities to act, and free will: the new dispositionalism. Mind, 118, 323–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108, 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demetriou, K. (2010). The soft-line solution to Pereboom’s four-case argument. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88, 595–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fara, M. (2008). Masked abilities and compatibilism. Mind, 117, 843–865.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2004). Responsibility and manipulation. The Journal of Ethics, 8, 145–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2008). Freedom, foreknowledge, and Frankfurt: a reply to Vihvelin. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 38, 327–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2010). The Frankfurt cases: the moral of the stories. The Philosophical Review, 119, 315–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: a theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Tognazzini, N. A. (2007). Exploring evil and philosophical failure: a critical notice of Peter van Inwagen’s The Problem of Evil. Faith and Philosophy, 24, 458–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. E. (2011). Masks, abilities, and opportunities: why the new dispositionalism cannot succeed. The Modern Schoolman, 88, 89–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, P., & Wettstein, H. K. (Eds.). (2006). Midwest Studies in Philosophy: shared intentions and collective responsibility, vol. 30, issue 1, 1–337.

  • Ginet, C. (1966). Might we have no choice? In K. Lehrer (Ed.), Freedom and determinism (pp. 87–104). New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (1998). Moral accountability. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2013). Historicism, non-historicism, or a mix? Journal of Ethics, 17, 185–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1979). ‘Could’, possible worlds, and moral responsibility. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 17, 345–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapitan, T. (2011). A compatibilist reply to the consequence argument. In R. Kane (Ed.), The oxford handbook of free will (2nd ed., pp. 131–150). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kittle, S. (2014). Vihvelin and Fischer on ‘Pre-decisional’ Intervention. Philosophia, 42, 987–997.

  • Lehrer, K. (1968). Cans without ifs. Analysis, 29, 29–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1976). ‘Can’ in theory and in practice: a possible worlds analysis. In M. Brand & D. Walton (Eds.), Action Theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2013). Manipulations for manipulation cases. Posted on Flickers of Freedom, June 13, 2013. Accessed on September 6, 2014 from: http://philosophycommons.typepad.com/flickers_of_freedom/2013/06/manipulations-for-manipulation-cases.html.

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Are we free to break the laws? Theoria, 47, 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1997). Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind, 117, 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2005). Where Frankfurt and Strawson meet. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2008). A hard-line reply to Pereboom’s four-case argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, 142–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Moral responsibility, manipulation arguments, and history: assessing the resilience of nonhistorical compatibilism. Journal of Ethics, 16, 145–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1995). Autonomous agents. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2005). A critique of Pereboom’s ‘four-case’ argument for incompatibilism. Analysis, 65, 75–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2013). Moral responsibility, manipulation, and minutelings. Journal of Ethics, 17, 153–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., & Lombrozo, T. (Manuscript). Effects of manipulation on attributions of causation, free will, and moral responsibility.

  • Nelkin, D. K. (2011). Making sense of freedom and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2008). Can’t we all just be compatibilists?: a critical study of John Martin Fischer’s “My Way”. The Journal of Ethics, 12, 157–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J., & Shaw, A. (2014). Manipulating morality: third-party intentions alter moral judgments by changing causal reasoning. Cognitive Science, 38, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2011). Actuality and responsibility. Mind, 120, 1071–1097.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2014). Vihvelin on Frankfurt-style cases and the actual-sequence view. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 1-14.

  • Saunders, J. T. (1968). The temptation of powerlessness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 5, 100–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shabo, S. (2010). Uncompromising source incompatibilism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 349–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2003). Rational capacities, or: how to distinguish recklessness, weakness, and compulsion. In Stroud & Tappolet (Eds.), Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality (pp. 17–38). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1994). The impossibility of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 75, 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2004). Free will demystified: a dispositional account. Philosophical Topics, 32, 427–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2013). Causes, laws, and free will: Why determinism doesn’t matter. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1975). Free agency. The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 517–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An early version of this paper was presented at the “Free Will and Moral Responsibility” summer school, hosted by the Moscow Center for Consciousness Studies; thanks to all participants in this group for helpful comments. Additionally, for helpful comments and discussion, I am grateful to Lorenza D’Angelo, John Fischer, Mark Heller, Sofia Jeppsson, Simon Kittle, Benjamin Matheson, Dan Miller, Matthew Talbert, Travis Timmerman, and an anonymous referee.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yishai Cohen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cohen, Y. The Manipulation Argument, At the Very Least, Undermines Classical Compatibilism. Philosophia 43, 291–307 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9583-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9583-9

Keywords

Navigation