Abstract
The novel approach presented in this paper accounts for the occurrence of the epistemic gap and defends physicalism against anti-physicalist arguments without relying on so-called phenomenal concepts. Instead of concentrating on conceptual features, the focus is shifted to the special characteristics of experiences themselves. To this extent, the account provided is an alternative to the Phenomenal Concept Strategy. It is argued that certain sensory representations, as accessed by higher cognition, lack constituent structure. Unstructured representations could freely exchange their causal roles within a given system which entails their functional unanalysability. These features together with the encapsulated nature of low level complex processes giving rise to unstructured sensory representations readily explain those peculiarities of phenomenal consciousness which are usually taken to pose a serious problem for contemporary physicalism. I conclude that if those concepts which are related to the phenomenal character of conscious experience are special in any way, their characteristics are derivative of and can be accounted for in terms of the cognitive and representational features introduced in the present paper.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
References
Biederman, I. (1987). Recognition-by-components: a theory of human image understanding. Psychological Review, 94, 115–147.
Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Chalmers, D. (2003). Consciousness and its place in nature. In S. Stich & T. Warfield (Eds.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of mind (pp. 102–142). Oxford: Blackwell.
Fodor, J. (1987). Why there still has to be a language of thought. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Psychosemantics (pp. 135–154). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (2008). LOT2—The language of thought revisited. Oxford: Clarendon.
Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.
Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary Didn't Know. The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 291–295.
Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and Qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.
Loar, B. (1990). Phenomenal states. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives (pp. 81–108). Northridge: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
Margolis, E. (1999). How to acquire a concept. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (Eds.), Concepts: core readings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Marr, D. (1982). Vision. A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Freeman.
Nida-Rümelin, M. (1996). What Mary couldn't know. In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Phenomenal consciousness. Schoenigh: Paderborn.
Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon.
Pylyshyn, Z. (2002). Mental imagery: in search of a theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25(2), 157–237.
Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing: it's not what you think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Bradford Books.
Shoemaker, S. (1981). The Inverted Spectrum. Journal of Philosophy, 74(7), 357–381.
Smith, A. D. (2010). Disjunctivism and Illusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(2), 384–410.
Stoljar, D. (2005). Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts. Mind and Language, 20, 469–494.
Acknowledgement
The present paper is an outcome of a collaboration with Zoltán Jakab. I am grateful to the University of Edinburgh College of Humanities and Social Sciences Scholarship and the Eötvös Scholarship from the Hungarian State for their generous support. Thanks to Jonas Christensen, Jesper Kallestrup, Andy Clark and an anonymous referee for their helpful comments. Special thanks to the organisers of the 2010 Rudolf Carnap Lecture and Graduate Workshop.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Fazekas, P. Cognitive Architecture and the Epistemic Gap: Defending Physicalism without Phenomenal Concepts. Philosophia 39, 21–29 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-010-9274-5
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-010-9274-5