Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Playing at Being Gods

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present article commences analyzing the origins and influences of the religious discourse on the configuration of the modern constitutional discourse and the contributions of the jus-positivism in the consolidation of this sacred-civil language. The second issue is the definition of the U.S. Constitution as a mixed and not as a democratic constitution, with regard to the influences of Plato, Aristotle, Cicero and Polybius to the Drafters of the first modern constitutional text; stability and equilibrium took preference over democracy in a wide sense. I also analyze how the Drafter’s decision has conditioned the modern constitutional system up to the present.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Explore related subjects

Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.

Notes

  1. About the theory of exclusive positivism and guidance see Marmor (2001), and Waluchow (1994).

    See also Gardner (2005), where he states that legal positivism is the thesis that in any legal system, whether a given norm is legally valid, and hence whether it forms part of the law of that system, depends of its sources.

  2. The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison).

  3. See, e.g., Declaration of the Independence, July 4, 1776, Preamble of the U.S. Constitution & Mc Culloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819), The Federalist Papers: 78 (Hamilton et al.).

  4. Rosenfeld et al. (2003). See Supra. P.3.

  5. The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison).

  6. Levinson 2006: 4. See also, Kammen (2006).

  7. Polybius 1962: 459. The Polybius notions of mob rule were well known to the Founders through discussion in Plutarch. See Clough (1885), Stourzh (1970), Hart (2004).

  8. The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison), see also Gilje (1987).

  9. Levinson (2006). See also Lazare (1996), Dahl (2003), Baker and Dinkin (1997), Rosenfeld (2004).

References

  • Ackerman, B. (1980). Social justice in the liberal state. New Haven: Yale University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1996). The politics and the constitution of Athens. New York: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. A., & Dinkin S. H. (1997). The senate: An institution whose time has gone? J.L. and Pol. 21.

  • Balkin, J. M. (2007). Original meaning and constitutional redemption. Constitutional Commentary, 24(2), 427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biondi, A. C. (2007). Aristotle on the mixed constitution and its relevance for American political thought. Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation.

  • Bulygin, E. (1998). An antinomy in Kelsen’s pure theory of law. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 297-317). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Burke, E. (1954). Reflexiones sobre la Revolución Francesa. Madrid (Spain): Instituto de Estudios Políticos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero. translation Clinton Walker Keyes De Re Publica, De Legibus, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1961.

  • Chemerinsky, E. (2006). Constitutional law, principles and policies (introduction to law series). New York, (NY): Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clough, A. H. (1885). Plutarch’s lives: The translation called Dryden’s. Boston, (MA): Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. (2003). How democratic is the American constitution?. New Haven: Yale University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (2005). Interpreting state constitutions: A jurisprudence of function in a federal system. Chicago: Univeristy of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilje, P. A. (1987). The road to Moboacry, popular disorder in New York City (pp. 1763–1834). Chapel Hill (NC): The University of North Carolina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, L. (1990). The judaic contribution to human rights. Can. Y.B. Int’l L, 28.

  • Greenidge, A. H. J. (1928). A handbook of Greek constitutional history. London (U.K.): Macmilland & CO., Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grey, T. C. (1984). The constitution as scripture. 37 Stan L. Rev 1,1-24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gummere, R. M. (1963). The American colonial. Mind and the classical tradition. Cambridge (Mass): Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, G. (2004). The restoration of the republic: The Jeffersonian idea in 21st century America. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, D. L. (2006). The faiths of the founding fathers. New York (NY): Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honoré, T. (1998). The basic norm of a society. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 89–113). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A., Madison, J., & Jay, J. The federalist papers, in http://avalon.law.yale.edu/18th_century/fed02.asp.

  • Jefferson, T. (1950). Thomas Jefferson to James Madison. In J. P. Boyd (Ed.), The papers of Thomas Jefferson. Princeton (NJ): Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kammen, M. (2006). A machine that would go of itself. Piscataway (NJ): Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay, R. S. (1998). American constitutionalism. In A. Larry (Ed.), Constitutionalism, philosophical foundations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. (1961). General theory of law and state. New York: Russell & Russell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleinhaus, E. A. (2000). History as precedent: The post-originalist problem in constitutional law. Yale Law Journal.

  • Lazare, D. (1996). The frozen republic: How the constitution is paralyzing democracy. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, S. J. (1998). Unenumerated constitutional rights and unenumerated biblical obligations: A preliminary Study in comparative Hermeneutics. 15 Const. Commentary 511.

  • Levinson, S. (1998). Constitutional faith. Princeton: Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. (2006). Our undemocratic constitution, where the constitution goes wrong (and how the people can correct it). New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, D. (1988). The origins of American constitutionalism. Baton Rouge (LA): Louisiana State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2001). Positive law & objective values. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxcy, Z. J. (1998). The story of law. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrow, G. R. (1993). Plato’s Cretan city, a historical interpretation of the laws. Princeton: Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priel, D. (2006). Trouble for legal positivism? Legal Theory, 12(12), 225–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polybius. (1962). The histories of Polybius, Volume I, translated from the text of F. Hultsch by Evelyn S. Shuckburgh. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Raz, J. (1998). Kelsen’s theory of the basic norm. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 47–69). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robles – Morchón, G. (2006). El derecho como texto, Navarra, Aranzadi.

  • Rosenfeld, M., Dorsen, N., Sajó, A., & Susanne, B. (2003). Comparative constitutionalism, cases and materials. St Paul, MN: Thomson West Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld, R. (2004). What democracy: The case for abolishing the United States senate. Harper’s Magazine, 35-44.

  • Sellers, M. N. S. (1994). American republicanism. New York: New York University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Z. (1966). The ancient world: Justice, heroism and responsibility. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stourzh, G. (1970). Alexander Hamilton and the idea of republican government. Palo Alto (CA): Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, H. (1918). Cicero a sketch of his life and works. Chicago: A.C. McClurg & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Fritz, K. (1958). The theory of the mixed constitution in antiquity: A critical analysis of Polybius' political ideas. New York: Columbia University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wachulow, W. J. (1994). Inclusive legal positivism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wines, E. C. (1853). Commentaries on the laws of the ancient Hebrews; with an introductory essay on civil society and government. Philadelphia: Presbyterian Board of Publication.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to James A Gardner, Bruce Ackerman and Rabbi Gerson Lerner for helpful conversations. I benefited enormously from written comments by Mark Tushnet and I am deeply thankful to him for his advice.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antoni Abad i Ninet.

Additional information

I consider in this paper that the American constitutionalism started in 1789 as a sort of big bang of the American constitutionalist experiment. Other authors might suggest that the American constitutional tradition might be more critically tied to the events and moral-religious-legal conflations leading to the execution of Charles I in 1649, in this sense see David L Holmes (2006) and Donald Lutz (1988).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Abad i Ninet, A. Playing at Being Gods. Philosophia 38, 41–55 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-009-9210-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-009-9210-8

Keywords

Navigation