Abstract
The present article commences analyzing the origins and influences of the religious discourse on the configuration of the modern constitutional discourse and the contributions of the jus-positivism in the consolidation of this sacred-civil language. The second issue is the definition of the U.S. Constitution as a mixed and not as a democratic constitution, with regard to the influences of Plato, Aristotle, Cicero and Polybius to the Drafters of the first modern constitutional text; stability and equilibrium took preference over democracy in a wide sense. I also analyze how the Drafter’s decision has conditioned the modern constitutional system up to the present.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.Notes
About the theory of exclusive positivism and guidance see Marmor (2001), and Waluchow (1994).
See also Gardner (2005), where he states that legal positivism is the thesis that in any legal system, whether a given norm is legally valid, and hence whether it forms part of the law of that system, depends of its sources.
The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison).
See, e.g., Declaration of the Independence, July 4, 1776, Preamble of the U.S. Constitution & Mc Culloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819), The Federalist Papers: 78 (Hamilton et al.).
Rosenfeld et al. (2003). See Supra. P.3.
The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison).
The Federalist Papers No. 10 (Madison), see also Gilje (1987).
References
Ackerman, B. (1980). Social justice in the liberal state. New Haven: Yale University.
Aristotle. (1996). The politics and the constitution of Athens. New York: Cambridge University.
Baker, L. A., & Dinkin S. H. (1997). The senate: An institution whose time has gone? J.L. and Pol. 21.
Balkin, J. M. (2007). Original meaning and constitutional redemption. Constitutional Commentary, 24(2), 427.
Biondi, A. C. (2007). Aristotle on the mixed constitution and its relevance for American political thought. Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation.
Bulygin, E. (1998). An antinomy in Kelsen’s pure theory of law. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 297-317). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Burke, E. (1954). Reflexiones sobre la Revolución Francesa. Madrid (Spain): Instituto de Estudios Políticos.
Cicero. translation Clinton Walker Keyes De Re Publica, De Legibus, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1961.
Chemerinsky, E. (2006). Constitutional law, principles and policies (introduction to law series). New York, (NY): Aspen Publishers.
Clough, A. H. (1885). Plutarch’s lives: The translation called Dryden’s. Boston, (MA): Little, Brown and Company.
Dahl, R. (2003). How democratic is the American constitution?. New Haven: Yale University.
Gardner, J. (2005). Interpreting state constitutions: A jurisprudence of function in a federal system. Chicago: Univeristy of Chicago Press.
Gilje, P. A. (1987). The road to Moboacry, popular disorder in New York City (pp. 1763–1834). Chapel Hill (NC): The University of North Carolina.
Green, L. (1990). The judaic contribution to human rights. Can. Y.B. Int’l L, 28.
Greenidge, A. H. J. (1928). A handbook of Greek constitutional history. London (U.K.): Macmilland & CO., Limited.
Grey, T. C. (1984). The constitution as scripture. 37 Stan L. Rev 1,1-24.
Gummere, R. M. (1963). The American colonial. Mind and the classical tradition. Cambridge (Mass): Cambridge University Press.
Hart, G. (2004). The restoration of the republic: The Jeffersonian idea in 21st century America. New York: Oxford University.
Holmes, D. L. (2006). The faiths of the founding fathers. New York (NY): Oxford University.
Honoré, T. (1998). The basic norm of a society. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 89–113). Oxford: Clarendon.
Hamilton, A., Madison, J., & Jay, J. The federalist papers, in http://avalon.law.yale.edu/18th_century/fed02.asp.
Jefferson, T. (1950). Thomas Jefferson to James Madison. In J. P. Boyd (Ed.), The papers of Thomas Jefferson. Princeton (NJ): Princeton University.
Kammen, M. (2006). A machine that would go of itself. Piscataway (NJ): Transaction Publishers.
Kay, R. S. (1998). American constitutionalism. In A. Larry (Ed.), Constitutionalism, philosophical foundations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University.
Kelsen, H. (1961). General theory of law and state. New York: Russell & Russell.
Kleinhaus, E. A. (2000). History as precedent: The post-originalist problem in constitutional law. Yale Law Journal.
Lazare, D. (1996). The frozen republic: How the constitution is paralyzing democracy. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Levine, S. J. (1998). Unenumerated constitutional rights and unenumerated biblical obligations: A preliminary Study in comparative Hermeneutics. 15 Const. Commentary 511.
Levinson, S. (1998). Constitutional faith. Princeton: Princeton University.
Levinson, S. (2006). Our undemocratic constitution, where the constitution goes wrong (and how the people can correct it). New York: Oxford University.
Lutz, D. (1988). The origins of American constitutionalism. Baton Rouge (LA): Louisiana State University.
Marmor, A. (2001). Positive law & objective values. New York: Oxford University.
Maxcy, Z. J. (1998). The story of law. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, Inc.
Morrow, G. R. (1993). Plato’s Cretan city, a historical interpretation of the laws. Princeton: Princeton University.
Priel, D. (2006). Trouble for legal positivism? Legal Theory, 12(12), 225–264.
Polybius. (1962). The histories of Polybius, Volume I, translated from the text of F. Hultsch by Evelyn S. Shuckburgh. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Raz, J. (1998). Kelsen’s theory of the basic norm. In S. L. Paulson & B. Litschewski Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms, critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes (pp. 47–69). Oxford: Clarendon.
Robles – Morchón, G. (2006). El derecho como texto, Navarra, Aranzadi.
Rosenfeld, M., Dorsen, N., Sajó, A., & Susanne, B. (2003). Comparative constitutionalism, cases and materials. St Paul, MN: Thomson West Group.
Rosenfeld, R. (2004). What democracy: The case for abolishing the United States senate. Harper’s Magazine, 35-44.
Sellers, M. N. S. (1994). American republicanism. New York: New York University.
Stewart, Z. (1966). The ancient world: Justice, heroism and responsibility. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Stourzh, G. (1970). Alexander Hamilton and the idea of republican government. Palo Alto (CA): Stanford University.
Taylor, H. (1918). Cicero a sketch of his life and works. Chicago: A.C. McClurg & Co.
Von Fritz, K. (1958). The theory of the mixed constitution in antiquity: A critical analysis of Polybius' political ideas. New York: Columbia University.
Wachulow, W. J. (1994). Inclusive legal positivism. Oxford: Clarendon.
Wines, E. C. (1853). Commentaries on the laws of the ancient Hebrews; with an introductory essay on civil society and government. Philadelphia: Presbyterian Board of Publication.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to James A Gardner, Bruce Ackerman and Rabbi Gerson Lerner for helpful conversations. I benefited enormously from written comments by Mark Tushnet and I am deeply thankful to him for his advice.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
I consider in this paper that the American constitutionalism started in 1789 as a sort of big bang of the American constitutionalist experiment. Other authors might suggest that the American constitutional tradition might be more critically tied to the events and moral-religious-legal conflations leading to the execution of Charles I in 1649, in this sense see David L Holmes (2006) and Donald Lutz (1988).
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Abad i Ninet, A. Playing at Being Gods. Philosophia 38, 41–55 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-009-9210-8
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-009-9210-8