Skip to main content
Log in

Consensus Building and Its Epistemic Conditions

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most of the epistemological debate on disagreement tries to develop standards that describe which actions or beliefs would be rational under specific circumstances in a controversy. To build things on a firm foundation, much work starts from certain idealizations—for example the assumption that parties in a disagreement share all the evidence that is relevant and are equal with regard to their abilities and dispositions. This contribution, by contrast, focuses on a different question and takes a different route. The question is: What should people actually do who find themselves in deep disagreement with others? And instead of building theory on some “firm foundation,” the paper starts from a specific goal—building consensus by creating new proposals—and asks, first, which actions are suitable to achieve this goal and, second, what are the epistemic conditions of these actions. With regard to the latter, the paper focuses on what has been called framing and reframing in conflict research, and argues that both metaphors need and deserve a suitable epistemological conceptualization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I have to thank here two anonymous reviewers. Each of them pointed out one of these counter arguments against Fogelin’s argument.

  2. See Habermas (1990 <1983>, p. 66), and Rehg (2003, p. 85).

  3. Habermas (1990  <1983>), especially pp. 67–68 and p. 70.

  4. I have to thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the important difference between the “window” and the “QLG” cases.

  5. Another possible anchor is Polanyi’s notion of “interpretative frameworks” (Polanyi 1964).

  6. I have to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for raising this question.

  7. I am focusing here on what Schön and Rein call “co-design” among policy adversaries. The authors mention also three further strategies to deal with contention that do not involve frame reflection or reframing: (a) continuation or escalation of the controversy; (b) a “marketing strategy”; and (c) negotiation that aims at a compromise (Schön and Rein 1994, p. 170).

References

  • Bar-Tal D (2007) Sociopsychological foundations of intractable conflicts. Am Behav Sci 50:1430–1453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson G (1972 <1955>) A theory of play and fantasy. In: Bateson G (ed) Steps to an ecology of mind. Chandler, San Francisco

  • Bryan TA, Wondolleck JM (2003) When irresolvable becomes resolvable: the quincy library group conflict. In: Lewicki RJ, Gray B, Elliott M (eds) Making sense of intractable environmental conflicts. Concepts and cases. Island Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A (2002) Social moral epistemology. Soc Philos Policy 19:126–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter SL, Kennedy WJD (1988) Managing public disputes: a practical guide to handling conflict and reaching agreements. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D, Lackey J (2013) The epistemology of disagreement: new essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crowley S, Gonnerman C, O’Rourke M (2016) Cross-disciplinary research as a platform for philosophical research. J Am Philos Assoc 2:344–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewulf A, Gray B, Putnam L, Lewicki R, Aarts N, Bouwen R, Van Woerkum C (2009) Disentangling approaches to framing in conflict and negotiation research: a meta-paradigmatic perspective. Hum Relat 62:155–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donohue WA, Rogan RG, Kaufman S (eds) (2011) Framing matters: perspectives on negotiation research and practice in communication. Peter Lang, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigenbrode SD, O’Rourke M, Wulfhorst JD, Althoff DM, Goldberg CS, Merrill K, Morse W, Nielsen-Pincus M, Stephens J, Winowiecki L, Bosque-Perez NA (2007) Employing philosophical dialogue in collaborative science. Bioscience 57:55–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman R, Warfield TA (2010a) Introduction. In: Feldman R, Warfield TA (eds) Disagreement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman R, Warfield TA (eds) (2010b) Disagreement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R, Ury W, Patton B (1991 <1981>) Getting to yes: negotiating agreement without giving. Penguin Books, New York

  • Fogelin R (1985) The logic of deep disagreements. Informal Logic 7:1–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert MA (1997) Coalescent argumentation. L. Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AI (1999) Knowledge in a social world. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AI, Blanchard T (2016) Social epistemology. In: The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social/. Accessed 9 Oct 2018

  • Gray B (2007) Frame-based interventions for promoting understanding in multiparty conflicts. In: Gössling T, Oerlemans L, Jansen R (eds) Inside networks. A process view on multi-organisational partnerships, alliances and networks. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1990 <1983>) Discourse ethics: notes on a program of philosophical justification. In: Moral consciousness and communicative action (Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln). MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass

  • Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (Faktizität und Geltung, 1992). MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2012) The righteous mind: why good people are divided by politics and religion. Pantheon Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann MHG (2011) Analyzing framing processes in conflicts and communication by means of logical argument mapping. In: Donohue WA, Rogan RG, Kaufman S (eds) Framing matters: perspectives on negotiation research and practice in communication. Peter Lang, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan DM (2013) Ideology, motivated reasoning, and cognitive reflection. Judgm Decis Mak 8:407–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewicki RJ, Gray B, Elliott M (eds) (2003) Making sense of intractable environmental conflicts: concepts and cases. Island Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Sperber D (2011) Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behav Brain Sci 34:57–74; 94–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton BG (2005) Sustainability. A philosophy of adaptive ecosystem management. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Rourke M, Crowley SJ (2013) Philosophical intervention and cross-disciplinary science: the story of the Toolbox Project. Synthese 190: 1937–1954

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Rourke M, Crowley S, Eigenbrode SD, Wulfhors JD (eds) (2014) Enhancing communication & collaboration in interdisciplinary research. SAGE, Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1964) Personal knowledge: towards a post-critical philosophy. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1971 <1951>) Two dogmas of empiricism. In: From a logical point of view: 9 logico-philosophical essays, 2nd ed. Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, MA

  • Rawls J (1993) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehg W (2003) Discourse ethics. In: Wyschogrod E, McKenny GP (eds) The ethical. Blackwell Pub., Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Rittel HWJ, Webber MM (1973) Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sci 4:155–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothman J (1997) Resolving identity conflicts in nations, organizations, and communities. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Schön DA, Rein M (1994) Frame reflection: toward the resolution of intractable policy controversies. BasicBooks, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz RM (2002) The skilled facilitator: a comprehensive resource for consultants, facilitators, managers, trainers, and coaches. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman SA, Fernbach P (2017) The knowledge illusion: why we never think alone. Riverhead Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R (2004) A systematic theory of argumentation: the pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel I, Royakkers L (2011) Ethics, technology, and engineering: an introduction. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen D (2007) The political brain: the role of emotion in deciding the fate of the nation. PublicAffairs, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen D, Blagov PS, Harenski K, Kilts C, Hamann S (2006) Neural bases of motivated reasoning: an fMRI study of emotional constraints on partisan political judgment in the 2004 US Presidential election. J Cogn Neurosci 18:1947–1958

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler M (1993) Regional consensus on affordable housing: yes in my backyard? J Plann Educ Res 12:139–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research has been supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation (Cyberlearning and Future Learning Technologies, Award 1623419). Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Science Foundation. I am thankful for feedback that Bryan Norton, Justin Biddle, Rafael Meza, Anne Zacharias-Walsh, and Daniel S. Schiff provided.

Funding

This study was funded by a grant from the National Science Foundation (Cyberlearning and Future Learning Technologies, Award 1623419).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael H. G. Hoffmann.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Author Michael Hoffmann declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hoffmann, M.H.G. Consensus Building and Its Epistemic Conditions. Topoi 40, 1173–1186 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09640-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09640-x

Keywords

Navigation