Advertisement

Topoi

pp 1–12 | Cite as

Aristotelian Causation and Neural Correlates of Consciousness

  • Matthew Owen
Article
  • 31 Downloads

Abstract

Neural correlates of consciousness (NCC) are neural states or processes correlated with consciousness. The aim of this article is to present a coherent explanatory model of NCC that is informed by Thomas Aquinas’s human ontology and Aristotle’s metaphysics of causation. After explicating four starting principles regarding causation and mind–body dependence, I propose the Mind–Body Powers model of NCC.

Keywords

Neural correlates of consciousness NCC Consciousness Aristotelianism Thomism Human ontology Causation Powers Mental powers 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I want to thank the Tiny Blue Dot Foundation for generously funding my work as the Elizabeth R. Koch Research Fellow for Tiny Blue Dot Consciousness Studies. I also want to thank my fellowship advisor, Christof Koch for constructive comments on an earlier version of this article and many helpful conversations. I am deeply grateful for Aryn Owen’s constructive feedback on my writing. Anna Marmodoro, Nikk Effingham, Jussi Suikkanen, Henry Taylor, Mihretu Guta, Daniel De Haan and an anonymous reviewer also provided very helpful feedback on previous versions of this article, for which I am grateful.

Funding

Research funded by the Tiny Blue Dot Foundation.

Compliance with Ethical Standards

Conflict of interest

The author, Matthew Owen, declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human Participants and/or Animals

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

References

  1. Allen Institute (2016) Allen Brain Atlas. Seattle, Allen Institute for Brain Science, https://www.brain-map.org
  2. Aquinas T (1947) Summa Theologica. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (trans) Benziger Bros edn. Christian Classics Ethereal LibraryGoogle Scholar
  3. Aquinas T (1975a) Summa Contra Gentiles, Book Two: Creation. Anderson JF (trans) University of Notre Dame Press, Notre DameGoogle Scholar
  4. Aquinas T (1975b) Summa Contra Gentiles, Book Four: Salvation. O’Neil CJ (trans) University of Notre Dame Press, Notre DameGoogle Scholar
  5. Aquinas T (1984) Questions on the soul. Robb JH (trans) Marquette University Press, MilwaukeeGoogle Scholar
  6. Aquinas T (2002) The treatise on human nature: Summa Theologiae 1a 75–89. Pasnau R (trans) Hackett Publishing Company, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  7. Barnes J (ed) (1984) The complete works of Aristotle: the revised Oxford translation. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  8. Chalmers DJ (1998) On the search for the neural correlate of consciousness. In: Hameroff SR, Kaszniak AW, Scott AC (eds) Toward a science of consciousness II: the second Tucson discussions and debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 219–229Google Scholar
  9. Chalmers DJ (2000) What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In: Metzinger T (ed) Neural correlates of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 17–40Google Scholar
  10. Choi S, Fara M (2016) Dispositions. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University, StanfordGoogle Scholar
  11. Cramer SC, Sur M, Dobkin BH et al (2011) Harnessing neuroplasticity for clinical applications. Brain 134:1591–1609CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Crick F, Koch C (1990) Toward a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Semin Neurosci 2:263–275Google Scholar
  13. des Chene D (2000) Life’s form: late Aristotelian conceptions of the soul. Cornell University Press, IthacaGoogle Scholar
  14. Feser E (2009) Aquinas: a beginner’s guide. Oneworld, LondonGoogle Scholar
  15. Freddoso AJ (2012) Oh My Soul, There’s Animals and Animals: Some Thomistic Reflections on Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Paper presented at the second Thomistic workshop, Mount Saint Mary College, Newburgh, June 2012Google Scholar
  16. Goodrich GL, Martinsen GL, Flyg HM et al (2013) Development of a mild traumatic brain injury-specific vision sceening protocal: a Delphi study. J Rehabil Res Dev 50(6):757–769CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Haldane J (1998) A return to form in the philosophy of mind. Ratio 11(3):253–277CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hume D (2007) An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  19. Jaworski W (2016) Structure and the metaphysics of mind: how hylomorphism solves the mind–body problem. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Koch C (2012) Consciousness: confessions of a romantic reductionist. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  21. Koch C, Massimini M, Boly M et al (2016) Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nat Rev Neurosci 17:307–321CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kripke S (1981) Naming and necessity. Blackwell, MaldenGoogle Scholar
  23. Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems: towards a theory of scientific growth. University of California Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
  24. Lowe EJ (1998) The possibility of metaphysics: substance, identity, and time. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  25. Lowe EJ (2006) Non-cartesian substance dualism and the problem of mental causation. Erkenntnis 65(1):5–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lowe EJ (2009) Dualism. In: McLaughlin BP, Beckermann A, Walter S (eds) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 66–84Google Scholar
  27. Madden JD (2013) Mind, matter, & nature: a thomistic proposal for the philosophy of mind. The Catholic University of American Press, Washington, D.C.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Marmodoro A (2014a) Aristotle on perceiving objects. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Marmodoro A (2014b) Causation without glue: Aristotle on causal powers. In: Viano C, Natali C, Zingano M (eds) Les Quatre Causes d’Aristotle: Origins et Interprétations. Peeters, Leuven, pp 221–246Google Scholar
  30. Marmodoro A, Page B (2016) Aquinas on forms, substances and artifacts. Vivarium 54:1–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Mayr E (2016) Powers in the history of modern metaphysics. Presentation for University of Oxford: powers structuralism in ancient ontologies, Neo-Aristotelian approaches to the metaphysics of the mind Summer School and Conference, Naples, Italy, 26 September–2 October 2016Google Scholar
  32. Metzinger T (2000) Introduction. In: Metzinger T (ed) Neural correlates of consciousness: empirical and conceptual questions. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  33. Moreland JP (2015) Tweaking Dallas Willard’s ontology of the human person. J Spirit Form Soul Care 8(2):187–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Moreland JP (2016) A critique of and alternative to Nancey Murphy’s Christian physicalism. Eur J Philos Relig 8(2):107–128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Moreland JP (2018) In defense of a Thomistic-like dualism. In: Loose JJ, Menuge AJL, Moreland JP (eds) The Blackwell companion to substance dualism. Wiley Blackwell, Oxford, pp 102–122CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Mormann F, Koch C (2007) Neural Correlates of Consciousness. ScholarpediaGoogle Scholar
  37. Munoz-Cespedes JM, Rios-Lago M, Paul N et al (2005) Functional neuroimaging studies of cognitive recovery after acquired brain damage in adults. Neuropsychol Rev 15(4):169–183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Murphy N (1998) Human nature: historical, scientific, and religious issues. In: Brown WS, Murphy N, Malony HN (eds) Whatever happened to the soul? Scientific and Theological Portraits of Human Nature. Fortress Press, MinneapolisGoogle Scholar
  39. Oderberg DS (2005) Hylemorphic dualism. In: Paul EF, Miller FD Jr, Paul J (eds) Personal identity. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 70–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Owen M (2019) Neural correlates of consciousness & the nature of the mind. In: Guta M (ed) Consciousness and the ontology of properties. Routledge, New York, pp 241–260Google Scholar
  41. Pasnau R (2002a) Commentary. In: Aquinas T. The Treatise on Human Nature: Summa Theologiae 1a 75–89. Pasnau R (trans) Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, pp 220–378Google Scholar
  42. Pasnau R (2002b) Intoduction. In: Aquinas T. The Treatise on Human Nature: Summa Theologiae 1a 75–89. Pasnau R (trans) Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, pp xii–xxiGoogle Scholar
  43. Pasnau R (2012) Philosophy of mind and human nature. In: Davies B, Stump E (eds) The Oxford handbook of Aquinas. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 348–368CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Pegis A (1974) The seperated soul and its nature in St Thomas. In: Maurer AA (ed) St Thomas Aquinas 1274–1974: commemorative studies. Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, Toronto, pp 131–158Google Scholar
  45. Pruss A (2013) Aristotelian forms and laws of nature. Analiza i Egzystencja 24:115–132Google Scholar
  46. Putnam H (1967) Psychological predicates. In: Capitan WH, Merrill DD (eds) Art, mind, and religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 37–48Google Scholar
  47. Ryle G (1949) The concept of the mind: 60th Anniversary edn. Routledge, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  48. Stump E (2003) Aquinas. Routledge, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  49. Tahko TE (2012) Contemporary Aristotelian metaphysics. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  50. Tononi G, Koch C (2015) Consciousness: here, there and everywhere? Philos Trans R Soc B 370:1–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Wippel J (2002) Thomas Aquinas on the seperated soul’s natural knowledge. In: McEvoy J, Dunne M (eds) Thomas Aquinas: approaches to truth, the Aquinas lectures at Maynooth 1996–2001. Four Courts Press, Portland, pp 114–140Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Gonzaga UniversitySpokaneUSA

Personalised recommendations