Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific Discovery Reloaded

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The way scientific discovery has been conceptualized has changed drastically in the last few decades: its relation to logic, inference, methods, and evolution has been deeply reloaded. The ‘philosophical matrix’ moulded by logical empiricism and analytical tradition has been challenged by the ‘friends of discovery’, who opened up the way to a rational investigation of discovery. This has produced not only new theories of discovery (like the deductive, cognitive, and evolutionary), but also new ways of practicing it in a rational and more systematic way. Ampliative rules, methods, heuristic procedures and even a logic of discovery have been investigated, extracted, reconstructed and refined. The outcome is a ‘scientific discovery revolution’: not only a new way of looking at discovery, but also a construction of tools that can guide us to discover something new. This is a very important contribution of philosophy of science to science, as it puts the former in a position not only to interpret what scientists do, but also to provide and improve tools that they can employ in their activity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Explore related subjects

Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.

Notes

  1. This theory, which of course stems from Freud, is a version of the out-of-mind view, as the person has no conscious awareness of, or control over, the links among ideas.

  2. This examination is not intended to be exhaustive: it analyses a few representative works of approaches that eased a new way of accounting for scientific discovery.

  3. A dedutive inference is obtained by using primitive rules whereby the content of their conclusion is literally included in their premises. A stock example is modus ponens (A, A → B ∴ B)—B is literally part of the second premise. Thus a deductive reasoning, as a chain of these basic rules, cannot expand logically the premises.

  4. Simon (Kulkarni and Simon 1988) relaxed the structures of BACON in later programs such as KEKADA, which, unlike BACON that “was concerned mainly with the ways in which theories could be generated from empirical data, with little or no help from theory” (Kulkarni and Simon 1988, 140), tries to deal with issues such as the question of where the data came from, the processes of designing experiments and programs of observation.

  5. I would like to thank Tom Nickles for a clarification of this point.

  6. See also (Gillies 2014 and Roberts 1989).

  7. This idea goes back to Plato, and Aristotle (see Quarantotto 2017) and has been re-proposed also recently (Laudan 1977, 1981; Nickles 1981; Cellucci 2017b).

  8. Plausible here, following Aristotle’s notion of andoxa, simply means that the arguments for the hypothesis are ‘stronger’ (in quality) than those against it on the basis of the existing knowledge.

  9. A positive heuristics guides us in the construction of admissible paths during the search of a solution for a problem. A negative heuristics prevents us from building certain paths—by blocking the modus tollens on a specific part of the theory.

  10. Stock examples are: change of unit of analysis, change of level of analysis, focus on processes vs focus on variables.

  11. An atomistic view of heuristics, that there is an ultimate, base set from which all others can be compounded, has also been put forward by Gigerenzer and Todd (see Gigerenzer et al. 1999).

  12. There are many examples of problems generated by heuristic procedures, like Poincaré’s conjecture.

References

  • Cellucci C (2013) Rethinking logic. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci C (2017a) Rethinking knowledge. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci C (2017b). Is mathematics problem solving or theorem proving?. Found Sci 22(1):183–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Clement JJ (2008) Creative model construction in scientists and students. The role of imagery, analogy, and mental simulation. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi M, Sawyer K (1995) Creative insight: the social dimension of a solitary moment. In: Steinberg RJ, Davidson JE (eds) The nature of insight. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 329–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1991). Frege. Philosophy of mathematics. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein A (1958) A testimonial. In: Hadamard J (ed) The psychology of invention in the mathematical field. Dover, Mineola, pp 142–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1960) The foundations of arithmetic. A logic-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. Harper, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Todd P, ABC Group (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies D (1996) Artificial intelligence and scientific method. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies D (2014) Serendipity and mathematical logic. In: Ippoliti E, Cozzo C (eds) From a heuristic point of view. Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Newcastle upon Tyne, pp 23–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory RL (1970) The intelligent eye. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory RL (1980) Perceptions as hypotheses. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 290:181–197

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz E (2007) Representation and productive ambiguity in mathematics and science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz E, Breger H (eds) (2000) The growth of mathematical knowledge. Springer, Dordercht

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadamard J (1958) The psychology of invention in the mathematical field. Dover, Mineola

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson N (1958) Patterns of discovery: an inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka J (1973) Logic, language-games and information. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2014) Reasoning at the frontier of knowledge. In: Ippoliti E (ed) Heuristic reasoning. Springer, Basel, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2017a) Building theories. The heuristic way. In: Dank D, Ippoliti E (eds) Building theories. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2017b). Heuristic logic. A kernel. In: Danks D, Ippoliti E (eds) Building theories. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E, Cellucci C (2016) Logica. Egea, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaccard J, Jacoby J (2010) Theory construction and model-building. Guilford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich A (1993) Scientific discovery: logic and tinkering. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich A (1994) Scientific discovery: a philosophical survey. Philosophia 23(1–4):3–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich A, Ne’eman Y (1989). Serendipity as a source of evolutionary progress in science. Stud Hist Philos Sci 20(4):505–529

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza J (1992) Genetic programming: on the programming of computers by means of natural selection, vol I, MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza J (1994) Genetic programming II: automatic discovery of reusable programs. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Koza J, Bennett III, Andre F, Keane D, M (1999) Genetic programming III: Darwinian invention and problem solving. Morgan Kaufmann, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulkarni D, Simon H (1988). The processes of scientific discovery: the strategy of experimentation. Cognitive Science, 12:139–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1976) Proofs and refutations: the logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb D, Easton SM (1984). Multiple discovery: the pattern of scientific progress. Avebury Publishing Company, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1981) A problem-solving approach to scientific progress. In: Hacking I (ed) Scientific revolutions. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 144–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Meheus J, Nickles T (eds) (2009) Models of discovery and creativity. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray P (1989) Genius: the history of an idea. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave A (1988). Is there a logic of scientific discovery?. LSE Q 2(3):205–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave A (1989) Deductive heuristics. In: Gavrovlu K, Goudaroulis Y, Nicolacopoulos P (eds) Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change. Kluwer, Boston, pp 15–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian N (2008) Creating scientific concepts. MIT Press, Cambridge (MA)

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A, Shaw JC, Simon HA (1958) Elements of a theory of human problem solving. Psychol Rev 65(3):151–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (ed) (1980a) Scientific discovery: logic and rationality. Springer, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (ed) (1980b) Scientific discovery: case studies. Springer, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (1981) What is a problem that we may solve it? Synthese 47(1):85–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (1985) Beyond divorce: current status of the discovery debate. Philos Sci 52(2):177–206

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (2009) The strange story of scientific method. In: Meheus J, Nickles T (eds) Models of discovery and creativity. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 167–207

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H (1908). L’invention mathématique. Enseignement mathématique 10:357–371

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1966) The Tacit Dimension. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1961) The logic of scientific discovery. Science Editions, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Quarantotto D (2017) Aristotle’s Problemata style and aural textuality. In: Polansky R, Wians W (eds) Reading Aristotle. Brill, Leiden, pp 75–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts RM (1989) Serendipity: accidental discoveries in science. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Rota GC (1997) Indiscrete thoughts. Birkhäuser, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley C (2003) Multiple analogies in science and philosophy. John Benjamins B.V, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H (1977) Models of discovery. Dordrecht, Reidel

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H (1987) Is scientific discovery a topic in the philosophy of science? In: Rescher N (ed) Scientific inquiry in philosophical perspective. University Press of America, Lanham, pp 1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H, Langley P, Bradshaw G, Zytkow J (1987) Scientific discovery: computational explorations of the creative processes. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Simonton DK (1988) Scientific genius: a psychology of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • von Helmholtz H (1866) Concerning the perceptions in general. In: Treatise on physiological optics, vol III. Dover, New York, pp 1–37

  • Wallas G (1926) The art of thought. Cape, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg R (2006) Creativity: understanding innovation in problem solving, science, invention, and the arts. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahar E (1983). Logic of discovery or psychology of invention?. British J Philos Sci 34:243–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahar E (1989) Einstein’s revolution. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Tom Nickles for all his support and advice in general (not only for this paper), and the anonymous referees for their comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emiliano Ippoliti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ippoliti, E. Scientific Discovery Reloaded. Topoi 39, 847–856 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9531-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9531-3

Keywords

Navigation