Advertisement

Topoi

, Volume 36, Issue 2, pp 331–342 | Cite as

Property-Awareness and Representation

  • Ivan V. Ivanov
Article

Abstract

Is property-awareness constituted by representation or not? If it were, merely being aware of the qualities of physical objects would involve being in a representational state. This would have considerable implications for a prominent view of the nature of successful perceptual experiences. According to naïve realism, any such experience—or more specifically its character—is fundamentally a relation of awareness to concrete items in the environment. Naïve realists take their view to be a genuine alternative to representationalism, the view on which the character of such experiences is constituted by representation. But naïve realists must admit qualities or property instances as items of awareness if they are to remain wedded to common sense, and the nature of property-awareness may smuggle constitutive representation into the naïve realist account of character. I argue that whether property-awareness involves representation, and consequently whether naïve realism is distinct from representationalism or not, depends on what qualities are fundamentally. On universalist and nominalist accounts, property-awareness turns out to involve representation. Not so under tropism.

Keywords

Naïve realism Representationalism Property-awareness Properties Universals Tropes Nominalism The argument from appearing 

References

  1. Armstrong DM (1978) Universals and scientific realism. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  2. Armstrong DM (1989) Universals: an opinionated introduction. Westview Press, BoulderGoogle Scholar
  3. Batty C (2010) What the nose doesn’t know: non-veridicality and olfactory experience. J Conscious Stud 17(3–4): 10–17Google Scholar
  4. Brewer B (1999) Perception and reason. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Brewer B (2006) Perception and content. Eur J Philos 14(2): 165–181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brewer B (2011) Perception and its objects. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Campbell K (1981) The metaphysic of abstract particulars. Midwest Stud Philos 6(1): 477–488CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Campbell K (1990) Abstract particulars. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  9. Campbell J (2002) Reference and consciousness. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Ehring D (2011) Tropes: properties, objects, and mental causation. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hellie B (2007) That which makes the sensation of blue a mental fact: moore on phenomenal relationism. Eur J Philos 15(3): 334–366CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Johnston M (2004) The obscure object of hallucination. Philos Stud 120(1–3): 113–183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Johnston M (2006) Better than mere knowledge? The function of sensory awareness. In: Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 260–290CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Johnston M (2007) Objective mind and the objectivity of our minds. Philos Phenomenol Res 75(2): 233–268CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Johnston M (2011) On a neglected epistemic virtue. Philos Issues 21(1): 165–218CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kennedy M (2009) Heirs of nothing: the implications of transparency. Philos Phenomenol Res 79(3): 574–604CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Martin MGF (2002) The transparency of experience. Mind Lang 4(4): 376–425CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Martin MGF (2010) What’s in a look? In: Nanay B (ed) Perceiving the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 160–225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. McDowell J (1994) Mind and world. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  20. McDowell J (1998) Having the world in view: Sellars, Kant, and intentionality. J Philos 95(9): 431–492Google Scholar
  21. Pautz A (2010) Why explain visual experience in terms of content? In: Nanay B (ed) Perceiving the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 254–309CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Price HH (1953) Thinking and experience. Hutchinson’s Press, LondonGoogle Scholar
  23. Rodriguez-Pereyra G (2002) Resemblance nominalism: a solution to the problem of universals. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Schellenberg S (2010) The particularity and phenomenology of perceptual experience. Philos Stud 149(1): 19–48Google Scholar
  25. Siegel S (2010) Do experiences have contents? In: Nanay B (ed) Perceiving the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 333–368CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Travis C (2004) The silence of the senses. Mind 113(449): 57–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Williams D (1953) On the elements of being: I. Rev Metaphys 7(1): 3–18Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of WarwickCoventryUK

Personalised recommendations