“If there is one thing in this world
that you can depend on,
that you can bet your last dollar on,
it’s the ignorance of the American people.”
-Pase Rock
Abstract
It is commonly held that political ignorance is rational, a response to the high costs and low benefits of acquiring political information. But many recent critics of the claim that political ignorance is rational instead urge that it is a simple consequence of agents not concerning themselves with the acquisition of political information whatsoever. According to such critics, political ignorance is inadvertent radical ignorance rather than a rational response to the incentives faced by agents in democracies. And since political ignorance is not a response to incentives, these critics urge, it cannot be ameliorated by incentivizing the acquisition of political information. This paper has two goals. First, I show that these seemingly competing accounts of political ignorance are in fact complementary, together explaining much political ignorance. Indeed, there is a sense in which political ignorance can be both rational and radical at the same time. Second, I more closely examine the relationship between incentives, kinds of political ignorance, and the acquisition of political information. On the one hand, from the fact that political ignorance is rational it does not follow that it can be overcome by incentivizing the acquisition of information. On the other hand, from the fact that political ignorance is radical it does not follow that it cannot be overcome by incentivizing the acquisition of information. Lastly, the complexity of the information in question is more relevant to determining whether ignorance can be overcome than whether such ignorance is rational or radical.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
Of course, this is consistent with there being some disagreement concerning the extent of such ignorance. See Lepoutre (2022) for relevant discussion.
This shouldn’t be taken to exclude the possibility that other factors play a role in exacerbating levels of political ignorance. For example, perhaps the prevalence of political misinformation also explains some public political ignorance. See Benkler, Faris, and Roberts (2018), Brown (2018), O’Connor and Weatherall (2019), Fritts and Cabrera (2022), Lynch (2022), and Gibbons (2023a; 2023b) for relevant discussion.
With that said, in Sect. 3 I suggest that even the models with the relevant assumptions capture the behavior of some agents.
See Somin (2021) for a helpful overview of many issues related to models of rational political ignorance.
For an overview of the epistemic demands placed upon agents by competing theories of democratic participation, see Somin (2013: pp. 38–61). Notably, on some theories, the sort of information mentioned above understates the amount of information required. If so, then the costs of information acquisition are even steeper than the preceding discussion suggests. For related discussion of the epistemic responsibilities of agents in democracies, see Boult (2021) and Giavazzi (2022).
There may even be straightforward monetary costs related to acquisition in some cases (for example, if the relevant information is behind a paywall, requires a subscription to access, and so forth), though the opportunity costs are more heavily emphasized in standard treatments of rational ignorance.
Precisely how unlikely voters are to cast a decisive vote, though an interesting question, is less important for our purposes than the fact that the relevant likelihood is assumed to be low and, more significantly, known—at least intuitively—by rational agents. On the probability of casting a decisive vote, see Ferejohn and Fiorina (1974), Owen and Grofman (1984), Aldrich (1993), and Gelman et al. (2012). See Somin (2013: pp. 62–4) for relevant discussion.
A closely related theory—rational irrationality—purports to explain the prevalence of seemingly widespread political irrationality in more-or-less the same way that a theory of rational ignorance explains the pervasiveness of political ignorance (Caplan, 2007). Broadly put, it holds that the costs of political rationality outweigh its benefits (and that the benefits of political irrationality outweigh its costs). And one might think that this theory ought to be considered alongside models of rational ignorance and radical ignorance as a possible explanation for high levels of political ignorance. However, I opt not to focus on it for two reasons. First, given the clear parallels between theories of rational ignorance and rational irrationality, it is plausible to assume that whatever applies to theories of rational ignorance also applies, at least in broad outline, to theories of rational irrationality. Moving forward, then, I assume that whatever is true of the comparative merits of theories of rational ignorance and radical ignorance (together with an assessment of their respective practical implications) is true of theories of rational irrationality and what we could call radical irrationality. Second, rational irrationality is of course best viewed as an account of political irrationality rather than political ignorance per se. Notably, not all politically irrational agents are politically ignorant, though (rational) political irrationality may explain the manner in which some political agents are selectively ignorant (Gibbons, 2022; Hannon, 2022). Thanks to an anonymous referee for discussion on this point.
Of course, if people find the process of acquiring information fun or entertaining, this also suggests that the costs of information acquisition are lower than they might initially seem, at least for some people.
Naturally, the political information acquired from entertaining sources is likely often to be of dubious quality.
For related discussion, see Gunn (2015: pp. 280–82).
Throughout this paper I write of political ignorance being “a choice”, being “chosen”, and so on. To clarify, when I say that political ignorance is chosen, I primarily have in mind cases where an agent is confronted with a range of alternatives and makes a conscious and deliberate choice of one alternative over the others. Specifically, these are cases where agents deliberately choose to forgo the acquisition of political information instead of some other alternative that involves the acquisition of information, and where the agent is aware of―and considering―the various alternatives. This contrasts with cases where an agent chooses to refrain from acquiring political information but without at the same time considering other alternatives involving the acquisition of information (as when I choose to listen to Thin Lizzy but without considering the possibility of listening to Motörhead instead). Thanks to an anonymous referee for pushing for clarity on this matter.
It is worth noting that not all proponents of rational ignorance models intend for these models to be psychologically realistic. Downs, for instance, writes that “[theoretical] models should be tested primarily by the accuracy of their predictions rather than by the reality of their assumptions” (Downs, 1957: p. 21). Others, most notably Milton Friedman (1953) and Satz and Ferejohn (1994), share similar methodological views. For such proponents of rational choice models, the challenge raised by proponents of radical ignorance misfires, since the relevant models are not intended to accurately capture the psychological profile of actual agents. However, other proponents of these models—such as Somin—do intend for their models to be empirically realistic (Somin, 2013: p. 89; though see also Somin, 2015: p. 382). For these proponents, the potential falsity of the relevant assumptions is an issue. See Hoffman (2015: p. 306) for further discussion.
It is notable―and admittedly controversial―that this way of characterizing rationality effectively makes rational choice a “theory of preference maximization” (Kogelmann and Gaus, 2017). It takes for granted an agent’s preferences, construing rationality as about, inter alia, always choosing the most preferred option from among a set of alternatives, and so on. For some, this way of viewing rationality may be somewhat unsatisfactory. Perhaps such people are drawn to the claim that rationality requires beliefs (and preferences) that are, in some sense, well-founded, rather than simply taking an agent’s preferences for granted (Gaus, 2008: pp. 9–12). However, in what follows, I adopt the approach to rationality utilized by scholars such as Downs and others who have argued that political ignorance is rational.
Indeed, some evidence indicates that people willingly give up a chance to win money in order to avoid being exposed to ideologically incongruent information (Frimer, Skitka, and Motyl, 2017). Relatedly, some people have belief-based preferences which lead them to seek out and process information in highly selective ways (Bénabou and Tirole, 2016). See Williams (2020a: pp. 5–7) for further discussion.
For a fascinating discussion of socially adaptive belief more generally, see Williams (2020b).
See Hertwig and Engels (2016), Gigerenzer and Garcia-Retamero (2017), and Brown and Walasek (2020) for sustained discussion of reasons people may have for remaining deliberately ignorant. For a more detailed investigation of deliberate ignorance, see the collection of articles in Hertwig and Engels (2020).
In a recent paper, Somin makes a similar claim about rational political ignorance, writing that “the prediction of rational behavior in this sphere is not dependent on the assumption that voters are hyper-logical or capable of making complex calculations about odds” (Somin, 2023: p. 289). Indeed, he elsewhere writes that precisely calculating overall costs and benefits is often irrational insofar as it takes more effort than it is worth to most agents (Somin, 2021: p. 242).
Tversky (1969), for instance, famously argues that, under certain conditions, intransitivity of preferences arises.
Cf. Bovens (2022) on the intransitivity of preferences.
Such people may have been influenced by these models to deliberately refrain from the acquisition of political information in ways they didn’t previously. Their political ignorance may even have been radical up until the point they first encountered models of rational ignorance, whereupon the option to acquire political information became salient for them, only to be rejected in favor of options involving deliberate ignorance.
In addition to the sources already mentioned earlier, see also Schwartz et al. (2020).
I assume here that the agents in question are typical adults. Children, for instance, especially young children, are likely to be radically ignorant of the overwhelming majority of politically relevant information.
See Lupia and Prior (2008) for some relevant experimental evidence in support of this claim.
Somin discusses some of these issues, concluding that “[at] the very least, we should devote more sustained analysis” to this sort of proposal (Somin, 2023: p. 300).
This is consistent with granting that such agents could be incentivized to acquire political information in some other fashion. However, it remains the case that institutionally realistic (i.e., legal, affordable, and practically implementable) ways of incentivizing the acquisition of political information may be ineffective for some people.
Of course, moving from one jurisdiction to another is costly. But political systems which enable a greater degree of foot voting make it less costly than it would be otherwise.
Thanks to Daniel Williams and two anonymous referees for their insightful feedback on different versions of this paper.
References
Aldrich, J. (1993). Rational choice and turnout. American Journal of Political Science, 37, 246–278.
Barnett, Z. (2020). Why you should vote to change the outcome. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 48, 422–446.
Bénabou, R., & Tirole, J. (2016). Mindful economics: the production, consumption, and value of beliefs. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30(3), 141–164.
Benkler, Y., Faris, R., & Roberts, H. (2018). Network propaganda: Manipulation, disinformation, and radicalization in american politics. Oxford University Press.
Bennett, S. E., & Friedman, J. (2008). The irrelevance of economic theory to understanding economic ignorance. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 20(1), 195–258.
Boult, C. (2021). The epistemic responsibilities of citizens in a democracy. In M. Hannon & J. de Ridder (Eds.), The routledge handbook of political epistemology. Routledge.
Bovens, L. (2022). Four structures of intransitive preferences. In C. M. Melenovsky (Ed.), The routledge handbook of philosophy, politics, and economics. Routledge.
Brennan, J. (2016). Against democracy. Princeton University Press.
Brennan, J., & Freiman, C. (2023). Why swing-state voting is not effective altruism: the bad news about the good news about voting. Journal of Political Philosophy, 31(1), 60–79.
Brown, E. (2018). Propaganda, misinformation, and the epistemic value of democracy. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 30(3–4), 194–218.
Brown, G. D. A., & Walasek, L. (2020). Models of deliberate ignorance in individual choice. In R. Hertwig & C. Engels (Eds.), Deliberate Ignorance: choosing not to know. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter. Princeton University Press.
Converse, P. E. (1964). The nature of belief systems in mass publics. In D. E. Apter (Ed.), Ideology and discontent. Free Press of Glencoe.
DelliCarpini, M. X., & Keeter, S. (1996). What Americans know about politics and why it matters. Yale University Press.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. Harper and Row.
Edlin, A., Gelman, A., & Kaplan, N. (2008). Vote for charity’s sake. The Economists’ Voice, 5, 1–4.
Evans, A. J., & Friedman, J. (2011). search versus browse: a theory of error grounded in radical (Not Rational) ignorance. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 23(1–2), 73–102.
Ferejohn, J., & Fiorina, M. (1974). The paradox of not voting: A decision theoretic analysis. American Political Science Review, 68, 525–536.
Friedman, J. (2005). Popper, weber, and hayek: The epistemology and politics of ignorance. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 17(1–2), 1–58.
Friedman, J. (2006). Taking ignorance seriously: Rejoinder to critics. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 18(4), 467–532.
Friedman, J. (2019). Power without knowledge: A critique of technocracy. Oxford University Press.
Friedman, M. (1953). The methodology of positive economics’, in essays in positive economics. University of Chicago Press.
Frimer, J. A., Skitka, L. A., & Motyl, M. (2017). Liberals and conservatives are similarly motivated to avoid exposure to one another’s opinions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 72, 1–12.
Fritts, M., & Cabrera, F. (2022). Fake news and epistemic vice: Combating a uniquely noxious market. Journal of the American Philosophical Association. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2021.11
Gaus, G. F. (2008). On philosophy, politics, and economics. Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
Gelman, A., Silver, N., & Edlin, A. (2012). What is the probability your vote will make a difference. Economic Inquiry, 50(2), 321–326.
Giavazzi, M. (2022). The epistemic responsibilities of voters: towards an assertion-based account. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 20(1–2), 111–131.
Gibbons, A. F. (2021). Political disagreement and minimal epistocracy. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 19(2), 192–201.
Gibbons, A. F. (2022). Is epistocracy irrational? Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 21(2), 251–281. https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v21i2.1581
Gibbons, A. F. (2023a). Bullshit in politics pays. Episteme. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2023.3
Gibbons, A. F. (2023b). Bad language makes good politics. Inquiry: an Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2023.2203164
Gigerenzer, G., & Garcia-Retamero, R. (2017). Cassandra’s regret: The psychology of not wanting to know. Psychological Review, 124, 179–196.
Gilens, M. (2001). Political Ignorance and collective policy preferences. American Political Science Review, 95(2), 379–396.
Guerrero, A. (2021). The epistemic case for non-electoral forms of democracy. In M. Hannon & J. de Ridder (Eds.), The routledge handbook of political epistemology. Routledge.
Gunn, P. (2015). Looking but not seeing: The (Ir)relevance of incentives to political ignorance. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 27(3–4), 270–298.
Hannon, M. (2022). Are knowledgeable voters better voters? Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 21(1), 29–54. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X211065080
Hardin, R. (2009). How do you know? The economics of ordinary knowledge. Princeton University Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35(4), 519–530.
Hertwig, R., & Engels, C. (2016). Homo ignorans: deliberately choosing not to know. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(3), 359–372.
Hertwig, R., & Engels, C. (2020). Deliberate ignorance: Choosing not to know. The MIT Press.
Hoffman, T. (2015). Rational choice and political irrationality in the new millennium. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 27(3–4), 299–315.
Ikeda, S. (2003). How compatible are public choice and austrian political economy? Review of Austrian Economics, 16, 63–75.
Jervis, R. (1998). System effects: Complexity in political and social life. Princeton University Press.
Kahan, D. (2017). The expressive rationality of inaccurate perceptions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences., 40, 26–28.
Kogelmann, B., & Gaus, G. (2017). Rational choice theory. In A. Blau (Ed.), Research methods in analytic political theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kogelmann, B., & Ogden, B. G. (2018). Enough and as good: A formal model of lockean first appropriation. American Journal of Political Science., 62(3), 682–694.
Kolodny, N. & Brunero, B. (2020) Instrumental Rationality, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/rationality-instrumental/
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin., 108, 480–498.
Kurzban, R. (2012). Why everyone (Else) is a hypocrite. Princeton University Press.
Lau, R. R., & Redlawsk, D. P. (2001). Advantages and disadvantages of cognitive heuristics in political decision making. American Journal of Political Science, 45(4), 951–971.
Lepoutre, M. (2022). Political understanding. British Journal of Political Science. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123422000023
Little, A. (2008). Democratic piety: Complexity, Conflict, and violence. Edinburgh University Press.
Lupia, A. (2016). Uninformed: Why people know so little about politics and what we can do about it. Oxford University Press.
Lupia, A., & McCubbins, M. (1998). The Democratic dilemma: Can citizens learn what they need to know? Cambridge University Press.
Lupia, A., & Prior, M. (2008). Money, time, and political knowledge: Distinguishing quick recall and political learning skills. American Political Science Review, 52(1), 169–183.
Lynch, M. (2022). Memes, misinformation, and political meaning. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 60(1), 38–56.
MacAskill, W. (2015). Doing good better: How effective altruism can help you make a difference. Penguin.
O’Connor, C., & Weatherall, B. (2019). The misinformation age: How false beliefs spread. Yale University Press.
Oppenheimer, D., & Edwards, M. (2012). Democracy despite itself: Why a system that shouldn’t work at all works so well. MIT Press.
Owen, G., & Grofman, B. (1984). To vote or not to vote: The paradox of nonvoting. Public Choice, 42, 311–325.
Page, S. E. (2010). Diversity and complexity. Princeton University Press.
Popkin, S. L. (1991). The reasoning voter: communication and persuasion in presidential campaigns. University of Chicago Press.
Reiss, J. (2021). Why do experts disagree? Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 32(1–3), 218–241.
Riker, W. H., & Ordeshook, P. (1968). A theory of the calculus of voting. American Political Science Review, 62(1), 24–42.
Satz, D., & Ferejohn, J. (1994). Rational choice and social theory. The Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 71–87.
Schumpeter, J. A. (1942). Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. Harper and Brothers.
Schwartz, B., Richerson, P. J., Berkman, B. E., Frankenreiter, J., Hagmann, D., Isaacowitz, D. M., Pachur, T., Schooler, L. J., & Wehling, P. (2020). The deep structure of deliberate ignorance: mapping the terrain. In R. Hertwig & C. Engels (Eds.), Deliberate ignorance: choosing not to know. The MIT Press.
Simler, K., & Hanson, R. (2017). The elephant in the brain. Oxford University Press.
Sinhababu, N. (2016). In defense of partisanship. In D. Killoren, E. Crookston, & J. Trerise (Eds.), Ethics in politics: new papers on the rights and obligations of political agents. Routledge.
Somin, I. (2008). Knowledge about ignorance: New directions in the study of political information. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 18(1–3), 255–278.
Somin, I. (2013). Democracy and political ignorance: why smaller government is better. Stanford University Press.
Somin, I. (2015). The ongoing debate over political ignorance: reply to my critics. Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society, 27(3–4), 380–414.
Somin, I. (2020). Free to move: Foot voting, migration, and political freedom. Oxford University Press.
Somin, I. (2021). Is political ignorance rational? In M. Hannon & J. de Ridder (Eds.), The routledge handbook of political epistemology. Routledge.
Somin, I. (2023). Top-down and bottom-up solutions to the problem of political ignorance. In H. Samaržija & Q. Cassam (Eds.), The epistemology of democracy. Routledge.
Stigler, G. J. (1976). The Xistence of X-Efficiency. American Economic Review, 66(1), 213–216.
Sweeny, K., Melnyk, D., Miller, W., & Shepperd, J. (2010). Information avoidance: Who, What, When, and Why. Review of General Psychology, 14(4), 340–353.
Tullock, G. (1972). Toward a mathematics of politics. University of Michigan Press.
Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 76(1), 31–48.
Van der Vossen, B. (2021). Property, the environment, and the lockean proviso. Economics & Philosophy, 37(3), 395–412. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267120000401
Von Hippel, W., & Trivers, R. (2011). The evolution and psychology of self-deception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences., 34(1), 1–16.
Williams, D. (2020a). Motivated Ignorance, rationality, and democratic politics. Synthese, 198, 7807–7827.
Williams, D. (2020b). Socially adaptive belief. Mind & Language, 36(3), 333–354.
Williams, D. (2021). Epistemic irrationality and the Bayesian brain. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science., 72(4), 913–938.
Wittman, D. (1995). The myth of democratic failure. University of Chicago Press.
Zaller, J. R. (1992). The nature and origins of mass opinion. Cambridge University Press.
Zolo, D. (1992). Democracy and complexity: a realist approach. The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
There is no conflict of interest to declare.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Gibbons, A.F. Political ignorance is both rational and radical. Synthese 202, 61 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04293-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04293-1