Abstract
Recent accounts of teleological naturalism hold that organisms are intrinsically goaldirected entities. We argue that supporters and critics of this view have ignored the ways in which it is used to address quite different problems. One problem is about biology and concerns whether an organism-centered account of teleological ascriptions would improve our descriptions and explanations of biological phenomena. This is different from the philosophical problem of how naturalized teleology would affect our conception of nature, and of ourselves as natural beings. The neglect of this metatheoretic distinction has made it difficult to understand the criteria we should use for evaluating proposals to naturalize teleology. We argue that a clearer distinction between scientific and philosophical contexts shows that we need more than one set of criteria for evaluating proposals to naturalize teleology, and that taking these into account might advance or dissolve recurring debates in the literature.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
This is due to the fact that, while some scholars are more explicit about the kinds of problems they take themselves to be answering, many are not (and this is precisely what we deem problematic). This may be because it is not always possible to pin down a single set of motivating factors for a framework, especially when it is developed by multiple scholars. Furthermore, a certain account of teleology may prove to be well suited for answering questions which its originators did not intend to answer.
It is worth noting that Deacon puts a strong processual understanding of emergence at the center of his project, going so far as to reinterpret constraints and work from an emergence perspective (Deacon, 2011, chap. 11). The overall picture one gets from Deacon’s project is therefore not merely an account of the emergence of life, but a metaphysics of nature as radically emergent and processual.
According to Deacon, his model resembles a kind of ‘non-parasitic virus’ (2021) rather than an autopoietic protocell.
Deacon sees the basic logic of teleodynamics as recurring nested levels of emergent dynamics, and key to eventually understanding the biological basis of the human mind (Deacon, 2011).
Agency is therefore much like fluid viscosity, which is considered a real phenomenon even though “it is not specified in terms of the properties of its molecular realizer but in terms of other concepts at the same gross dynamical scale, such as density or surface tension.” (Fulda, 2017, p. 82; see also Walsh, 2018, pp. 171–172). Fluid viscosity, on this view, is a natural phenomenon because it is an indispensable explanans in the prediction and explanation of fluid behavior (Fulda, 2017, p. 83).
Though this approach is the least ‘organism-centered’ of those we are discussing here, we include it insofar as it is “an account of teleological systems, not an account of function” (Babcock & McShea, 2021, p. 8766).
This distinction is similar to, but arguably distinct from, Price et al.’s (2013) distinction between “object naturalism” and “subject naturalism”, since subject naturalism can include what the sciences say about human cognitive capacities and incapacities.
Ellis (2014), for instance, suggests that McDowell’s arguments for the reality of value in a suitably expanded naturalism can also be used to expand naturalism even further to include God.
We say “contemporary liberal naturalism” because liberal naturalism has mid twentieth century antecedents that have today fallen into relative obscurity; see Krikorian (1944)
We also think that the case of teleology and biological individuality would mirror each other insofar as the relationship between theory and practice would be symmetrical, with both sides ought to have input on the debate, change it in the process (Love, 2018, p. 170).
We are, in effect, suggesting that advancing these kinds of debates require something like what Godfrey-Smith (2001) and Brancazio and Meyer (2022) call “philosophy of nature” though they use the term to label schools of thought (such as enactivism) rather than questions, which is our preferred framing of the issue.
As Fox-Keller (2003) argues, terminological ambiguity has in the past been essential to the establishment of a global narrative relating different biological phenomena, and thereby advancing research.
It is also possible for closure of constraints might play different roles in different contexts, such as those described in Sects. 3.1 and 3.2. But where closure of constraints may have strengths in one context, we expect it to have weaknesses in another. One may want to leverage it to make more radical statements about the ontology of living systems, and in this context Cusimano and Sterner’s worries would take on a different hue. Furthermore, it is not necessarily the case that closure would be able to play no other role than one of a model in practice. These are the kinds of questions that we believe are in urgent need of elaboration (see Bich & Mossio, 2014).
We find it revealing that the authors suggest they are solving ‘the philosophical problem of teleology’ in the singular, and without specifying what, exactly, they take this problem to be. The authors seem to think —though it is never clear—that this apparently singular problem has to do solely with advancing biology, and should be evaluated on those terms. But as we argued in the previous section, this is far from self-evident and cannot be assumed.
The idea being that a heat-seeking missile would be goal-directed in the same way as a bacterium, insofar as they are both directed by environmental fields (heat and sucrose gradients respectively).
This is not to say that the explanatory success of a model of teleology should have no impact on broader philosophical questions. It is simply that the relation between these areas, in our view, is far more complex than McShea and Babcock assume it to be.
Besides, they make these claims despite never defining the standards by which they deem their explanation successful.
Garcia-Valdecasas refers to this as “an illuminating principle that was lost in modernity” (ibid). At stake in teleology is therefore far more than what biology needs, but also an implicit critique of modernity in the style of Jonas (2001).
On the face of it, a second-order constraint would have to be constituted by interlocking constraints—otherwise it would not be a second order constraint, a constraint that constrains constraints. In other words, we are inclined to think that the OA does account for second-order constraints, though it does not emphasize, as Deacon does, the importance of two different kinds of self-organizing systems that are mutually inhibiting.
For those familiar with Deacon’s project, the teleodynamic level constrains the morphodynamic and homodynamic levels below it; see the discussion of Deacon in Sect. 1.
While the Organizational Approach does appeal to a certain conception of normativity, we find it to be thinner than Garcia-Valdecasas’s for the reasons described above.
Notice that it would not suffice to simply point out, as Garcia-Valdecasas does, that Kant takes teleology to be a subjective heuristic that our finite minds cannot avoid; one can be a realist about teleology in Kant’s sense (Gambarotto & Nahas, 2022), which means that one need not be an Aristotelian about teleology to be a teleological realist.
References
Aaby, B. H., & Desmond, H. (2021). Niche construction and teleology: Organisms as agents and contributors in ecology, development, and evolution. Biology & Philosophy, 36(5), 47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09821-2
Ashby, W. R. (1960). Design for a brain: The origin of adaptive behaviour. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-1320-3
Atkins, P. W. (1984). The Second Law (1st ed.). Scientific American Books - W. H. Freeman & Co.
Ayala, F. J. (1970). Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 37(1), 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1086/288276
Babcock, G., & McShea D. (2021). An externalist teleology. Synthese, 199(3): 8755–80. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03181-w.
Baedke, J. (2019). O organism, where art thou? Old and new challenges for organism-centered biology. Journal of the History of Biology, 52(2), 293–324. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-018-9549-4
Baedke, J., Fábregas-Tejeda, A., & Prieto, G. I. (2021). Unknotting reciprocal causation between organism and environment. Biology & Philosophy, 36(5), 48. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09815-0
Baedke, J., Fábregas-Tejeda, A., & Vergara-Silva, F. (2020). Does the extended evolutionary synthesis entail extended explanatory power? Biology & Philosophy, 35(1), 20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-9736-5
Bechtel, W., & Bich, L. (2021). Grounding cognition: Heterarchical control mechanisms in biology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society b: Biological Sciences, 376(1820), 20190751. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0751
Beckner, M. (1969). Function and teleology. Journal of the History of Biology, 2(1), 151–164. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00137271
Bernstein, J. M. (2002). Re-enchanting nature. In N. Smith (Ed.), Reading McDowell (pp. 229–257). Routledge.
Bich, L. (2012). Complex emergence and the living organization: An epistemological framework for biology. Synthese, 185(2), 215–232. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9722-6
Bich, L., Mossio, M., & Soto, A. M. (2020). Glycemia regulation: From feedback loops to organizational closure. Frontiers in Physiology, 11, 69. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2020.00069
Bilgrami, A. (2011). The wider significance of naturalism: A genealogical essay. Balkan Journal of Philosophy III, 1, 23–40.
Cusimano, S., & Sterner, B. (2020). The objectivity of organizational functions. Acta Biotheoretica, 68(2), 253–269. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-019-09365-9
De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (Eds.). (2010). Naturalism and normativity. Columbia themes in philosophy. Columbia University Press.
Deacon, T. W. (2011). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter (1st ed.). W.W. Norton & Co.
Deacon, T. W. (2015). Steps to a science of biosemiotics. Green Letters, 19(3), 293–311. https://doi.org/10.1080/14688417.2015.1072948
Deacon, T. W. (2021). How molecules became signs. Biosemiotics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-021-09453-9
Deacon, T. W., & Cashman, T. (2013). Teleology versus mechanism in biology: beyond self-organization. In A. C. Scarfe & B. G. Henning (Eds.), Beyond mechanism: Putting life back into biology (pp. 290–311). Lexington Books.
Deacon, T. W., & Cashman, T. (2016). Steps to a metaphysics of incompleteness. Theology and Science, 14(4), 401–429. https://doi.org/10.1080/14746700.2016.1231977
Deacon, T. W., Srivastava, A., & Bacigalupi, J. A. (2014). The transition from constraint to regulation at the origin of life. Frontiers in Bioscience, 19, 945–957.
Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9002-y
Dobzhansky, T. (1973). Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher, 35(3), 125–129. https://doi.org/10.2307/4444260
Eldredge, N., & Gould, S. J. (1989). APPENDIX: punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. In N. Eldredge (Ed.), Time Frames (pp. 193–224). Princeton University Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400860296.193
Ellis, F. (2014). God, value, and nature. Oxford University Press.
Esposito, M. (2013). Heredity, development and evolution: The unmodern synthesis of E.S. Russell. Theory in Biosciences, 132(3), 165–180. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-013-0177-4
Fábregas-Tejeda, A., & Vergara-Silva, F. (2018). The emerging structure of the extended evolutionary synthesis: Where does evo-devo fit in? Theory in Biosciences, 137(2), 169–184. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-018-0269-2
Fulda, F. C. (2017). Natural agency: The case of bacterial cognition. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(1), 69–90. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2017.5
Gallagher, S. (2018). Rethinking nature: Phenomenology and a non-reductionist cognitive science. Australasian Philosophical Review, 2(2), 125–137. https://doi.org/10.1080/24740500.2018.1552074
Gambarotto, A., & Mossio, M. (2022). Enactivism and the Hegelian stance on intrinsic purposiveness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, July. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09823-9
Gambarotto, A., & Nahas, A. (2022). Teleology and the organism: Kant’s controversial legacy for contemporary biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 93, 47–56. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2022.02.005
Gambarotto, A., & Nahas, A. (2023). Nature and agency: Towards a post-Kantian naturalism. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09882-w
García-Valdecasas, M. (2021). On the naturalisation of teleology: Self-organisation, autopoiesis and teleodynamics. Adaptive Behavior. https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712321991890
Garson, J. (2016). A critical overview of biological functions. (1st ed.). Philosophy of Science. Springer . https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32020-5
Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2019). Learning and the origins of consciousness. MIT Press.
Giovanni, P., & Michael, L. (2016). Top-down models in biology: explanation and control of complex living systems above the molecular level. Journal of The Royal Society Interface 13(124), 20160555. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2016.0555
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2001). On the status and explanatory structure of developmental systems theory. In Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 283–297). MIT Press.
Jaeger, J. (2022). The fourth perspective: Evolution and organismal agency. In M. Mossio (Ed.), Organization in biology. Springer.
Jonas, H. (2001). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Northwestern University Press.
Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment. Translated by P. Guyer and E. Matthews. Cambridge University Press.
Kauffman, S. A. (1993). The origins of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press.
Kauffman, S. A. (2000). Investigations. Oxford University Press.
Keller, E. F. (2003). Making sense of life: Explaining biological development with models, metaphors, and machines. Harvard Univ. Press.
Krikorian, Y. H. (1944). Naturalism and the human spirit. Columbia University Press.
Kovaka, K. (2015). Biological individuality and scientific practice. Philosophy of Science, 82(5), 1092–1103.
Laland, K. N., Uller, T., Feldman, M. W., Sterelny, K., Müller, G. B., Moczek, A., Jablonka, E., & Odling-Smee, J. (2015). The extended evolutionary synthesis: Its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 282(1813), 20151019. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2015.1019
Lee, J. G., & McShea, D. W. (2020). Operationalizing goal directedness: An empirical route to advancing a philosophical discussion. Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology. https://doi.org/10.3998/ptpbio.16039257.0012.005
Levin, M. (2019). The computational boundary of a ‘self’: Developmental bioelectricity drives multicellularity and scale-free cognition. Frontiers in Psychology, 10, 2688. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02688
Levins, R., & Lewontin, R. C. (2009). The dialectical biologist. Aaker Books.
Lewens, T. (2019). The extended evolutionary synthesis: What is the debate about, and what might success for the extenders look like? Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 127(4), 707–721. https://doi.org/10.1093/biolinnean/blz064
Love, A. C. (2018). Individuation, individuality, and experimental practice in developmental biology. In O. Bueno, R. Chen, & M. B. Fagan (Eds.), Individuation, process, and scientific practices. Oxford University Press.
Lovibond, S. (2006). Practical reason and its animal precursors. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(2), 262–273. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2006.00225.x.
Lyon, P. (2015). The cognitive cell: Bacterial behavior reconsidered. Frontiers in Microbiology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fmicb.2015.00264
Macarthur, D. (2019). Liberal naturalism and the scientific image of the world. Inquiry, 62(5), 565–585. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2018.1484006
Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science (Vol. 42). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8947-4
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Harvard University Press.
McShea, D. W. (2012). Upper-directed systems: A new approach to teleology in biology. Biology & Philosophy, 27(5), 663–684. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9326-2
Meyer, R., & Brancazio, N. (2022). Putting down the revolt: Enactivism as a philosophy of nature. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.948733
Mitchell, S. D. (2009). Unsimple truths: Science, complexity, and policy. The University of Chicago Press Chicago and London.
Montévil, M., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological organisation as closure of constraints. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 372, 179–191. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jtbi.2015.02.029
Mossio, M., & Bich, L. (2017). What makes biological organisation teleological? Synthese, 194(4), 1089–1114. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0594-z
Meyer, R., & Brancazio, N. (2022). Putting down the revolt: Enactivism as a philosophy of nature. Frontiers in Psychology, 13. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.948733.
Mossio, M., & Bich, L. (2014). La circularité biologique: Concepts et modèles. In F. Varenne, M. Silberstein, S. Dutreuil, & P. Huneman (Eds.), Modéliser & simuler. Epistémologies et pratiques de la modélisation et de la simulation (Vol. 2, pp. 137–170). Editions Matériologiques.
Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological Autonomy: A Philosophical and Theoretical Enquiry , 12. Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9837-2
Okrent, M. (2018). Nature and normativity: Biology, teleology, and meaning. Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy (p. 100). Routledge.
Pattee, H. H. (1977). Dynamic and linguistic modes of complex systems. International Journal of General Systems, 3(4), 259–266. https://doi.org/10.1080/03081077708934771
Potochnik, A. (2017). Idealization and the aims of science. University of Chicago Press. https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226507194.001.0001
Price, H., & Jackson, F. (1997). Naturalism and the fate of the M-worlds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 71, 247–282.
Price, H., Simon B., Brandom R., Horwich P., & Williams M. (2013). Expressivism, Pragmatism and Representationalism. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Company.
Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1984). Order out of chaos: Man’s new dialogue with nature. Bantam Books.
Rosen, R. (1985). Organisms as causal systems which are not mechanisms: an essay into the nature of complexity. In Theoretical biology and complexity (pp. 165–203). Elsevier.
Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, purpose and teleology. Philosophy in Science, 10(1), 18–24. https://doi.org/10.1086/286788
Rouse, J. (2015). Articulating the world: Conceptual understanding and the scientific image. University of Chicago Press.
Rouse, J. (2022). Liberal or radical naturalism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of liberal naturalism. Routledge.
Rupik, G. (2023). Evolutionary metamorphic organicism: A romantic philosophy of biology for the twenty-first century. PhD Dissertation (University of Toronto).
Sachs, C. (2012). Resisting the disenchantment of nature: McDowell and the question of animal minds. Inquiry, 55(2): 131–47. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2012.661576.
Schrödinger, E. (1992). What is life? With mind and matter and autobiographical sketches. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139644129
Sonnenschein, C., & Soto, A. M. (2016). Carcinogenesis explained within the context of a theory of organisms. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 122(1), 70–76. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2016.07.004
Soto, A. M., Longo, G., Montévil, M., & Sonnenschein, C. (2016). The biological default state of cell proliferation with variation and motility, a fundamental principle for a theory of organisms. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 122(1), 16–23. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2016.06.006
Sultan, S. E., Moczek, A. P., & Walsh, D. (2021). Bridging the explanatory gaps: What can we learn from a biological agency perspective? BioEssays. https://doi.org/10.1002/bies.202100185
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Walsh, D. (2015). Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press.
Walsh, D. (2018). Objectcy and agency: towards a methodological vitalism. In D. J. Nicholson & J. A. Dupre (Eds.), Everything flows (p. 416). Oxford University Press.
Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press.
Winther, R. G. (2020). When maps become the world. University of Chicago Press. https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226674865.001.0001
Wright, L. (1973). Function. Philosophical Review, 82, 139–168.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank Alan Love, Denis Walsh, David Harrison, Alejandro Fábregas-Tejeda, and two anonymous reviewers for their invaluable advice and feedback on previous versions of this manuscript.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
The authors declare that they have no competing interest.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Nahas, A., Sachs, C. What’s at stake in the debate over naturalizing teleology? An overlooked metatheoretical debate. Synthese 201, 142 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04147-w
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04147-w