Skip to main content
Log in

Measuring republican freedom

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Republican and so-called independence conceptions of freedom stand out from other conceptions by embedding strong modal conditions on what it takes for a person to count as being free to do something. For this reason, the extent of one’s freedom, conceived under republican/independentist lights, cannot be measured by any of the measures of freedom that have been developed so far in the literature on freedom, since these do not register the requisite modal constraints. In this paper I propose a measure of freedom that does capture the requisite modal concerns. I do so by relying on work in the semantics of counterfactuals to define a measure of how modally robustly available an option is to an individual.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The reader might protest that not every theory of counterfactual semantics postulates a tetradic similarity relation. Most only postulate a binary similarity relation. This is true, but the binary relations that are generally postulated already define certain tetradic similarity relations. So I am not assuming more than anyone’s view already implies. For example, Lewis postulates a binary ordering relation for every possible world, noted \(\trianglelefteq _i\), where i is the world in question. Given this family of orderings, one can stipulate that if \(w_1\trianglelefteq _1 w_2, w_3\trianglelefteq _3 w_4, w_2\bowtie _1w_3,\) and \(w_1\trianglelefteq _3w_4\), then \((w_1,w_2)\trianglelefteq (w_3,w_4).\)

  2. Note that d is always defined because any subset of N is bounded because N itself is bounded, and therefore the set of boundary points of any subset of N is a closed and bounded set. And since any closed and bounded set has an element least distant from 0, there is a boundary point nearest to the origin.

  3. Note that the distinction between a particular option and an opportunity set roughly maps on to the distinction Carter (1999) draws between specific freedoms and overall freedom. A specific freedom is the freedom to do some specific thing, e.g. eat an apple strudel and then do handstand, while overall freedom refers how all the specific freedoms each person enjoys aggregate to determine who is freer than whom, in a general sense. In our setup, an option is a specific freedom, and the ranking of opportunity sets is the overall freedom ranking.

  4. Formally speaking, these two requirements amount to just one requirement, namely, that overall freedom be strictly increasing in the membership grade of each option: i.e., given (Xm), (Xf), if \(m(x)\ge f(x)\) for all x, then \((X,m)\succsim (X,f).\) If, moreover, there is an x such that \(m(x)> f(x)\), then \((X,m)\succ (X,f).\)

  5. Formally: given four opportunity sets (Xm), (Xf), (Xg), (Xh), if \(m(x)=f(x)\iff g(x)=h(x)\) and for any x such that \(m(x)\ne f(x), m(x)=g(x)\iff f(x)=h(x)\), then \((X,m)\succsim (X,f)\iff (X,g)\ge (X,f).\) This property effectively guarantees, given completeness and a technical assumption of continuity, that the ranking of individual freedom can be represented by an additive function.

  6. Formally, this amounts to a symmetry requirement: given (Xm), (Xg), if there is a map \(\sigma \) from X to itself such that \(m(x)=g(\sigma (x))\) then \((X,m)=(X,g).\)

  7. Indeed, well-known results from social choice theory establish that a separable, complete, symmetric, complete, continuous, and monotonic preorder over a finite set of more than two objects is representable by a real-valued function which is decomposable into a sum of non-convex functions over each of its arguments [see Blackorby et al. (2005, Ch. 4) for rigorous formal treatment, or Hirose (2014, Ch. 2) for more intuitive discussion]. The rule I propose only assumes the special case in which these functions are in addition non-concave.

  8. Granted, I don’t know how much divergence I would expect between the robustness of the freedom to \(\phi \) and the improbability of my being prevented from \(\phi \)-ing. The modal robustness of a property and its chance of being observed are not independent: for example, if it’s impossible to prevent me from drinking tea, then the probability that I will be prevented from drinking tea is zero, and my freedom to drink tea is maximally robust. Thus, although robustness and probability can in principle come apart, it might be that my republican measure of freedom and Carter’s liberal measure of freedom end up converging in most actual cases.

References

  • Berlin, I. (1969). Two conceptions of liberty. In Four essays on liberty (pp. 118–172). Oxford University Press.

  • Bervoets, S., & Gravel, N. (2007). Appraising diversity with an ordinal notion of similarity: An axiomatic approach. Mathematical Social Sciences, 53, 259–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby, C., Bossert, W., & Donaldson, D. (2005). Population issues in social choice theory, welfare economics, and ethics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, I. (1999). A measure of freedom. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, I., & Schnayderman, R. (2019). The impossibility of freedom-as-independence. Political Studies Review, 17(2), 61–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Côté, N. (2020). Weakness of will and the measurement of freedom. Ethics, 130(3), 384–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, M., & Cox, T. (2008). Multidimensional scaling. In Handbook of data visualization. Berlin: Springer Handbooks Comp. Statistics. Springer.

  • Chang, R. (2015). Value in comparability and in commensurability. In I. Hirose & J. Olson (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of value theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1954). Classic and current notions of ‘measurable utility’. The Economic Journal, 64(255), 528–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirose, I. (2014). Moral aggregation. Oxford University Press.

  • Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. (2003). The quality of freedom. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M. (1979). A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility’’. Econometrica, 47, 565–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Valentini, L. (2016). Freedom as independence. Ethics, 121(4), 1043–1074.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Puppe, C. (1996). An axiomatic approach to “preference for freedom of choice”. Journal of Economic Theory, 68(1), 174–199.

  • Pattanaik, P. K., & Yongsheng, X. (1990). On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice. Recherches Économiques de Louvain, 56, 383–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattanaik, P. K., & Yongsheng, X. (2015). Freedom and its value. In I. Hirose & J. Olson (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of value theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1997). Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2012). Just freedom: A moral compass for society. WW Norton & Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2014). On the people’s terms: A republican theory and model of democracy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1976). Interpersonal aggregation and partial comparability. Econometrica, 38(3), 393–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Penguin Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. American Philosophical Quarterly, Monograph Series, 2, 98–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (1983). How free: Computing personal liberty. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, 15, 73–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1985). What’s wrong with negative liberty. Philosophy and the human sciences: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 211–29). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Funding was provided by SSHRC.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicolas Côté.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

For their insightful comments and feedback, I would like to thank Alex Voorhoeve, Campbell Brown, Ralf Bader, Bob Sugden, John Weymark, Alan Háyek, two anonymous reviewers, and audiences at the LSE’s Choice Group and the 2021 CPA. Thanks also to Philip Pettit, for many helpful conversations that helped me develop my ideas.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Côté, N. Measuring republican freedom. Synthese 200, 486 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03964-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03964-9

Keywords

Navigation