Abstract
The prediction error minimization framework (PEM) denotes a family of views that aim at providing a unified theory of perception, cognition, and action. In this paper, I discuss some of the theoretical limitations of PEM. It appears that PEM cannot provide a satisfactory explanation of motivated reasoning, as instantiated in phenomena such as self-deception, because its cognitive ontology does not have a separate category for motivational states such as desires. However, it might be thought that this objection confuses levels of explanation. Self-deception is a personal level phenomenon, while PEM offers subpersonal explanations of psychological abilities. Thus, the paper examines how subpersonal explanations couched in the PEM framework can be thought of as related to personal level explanations underlying self-deception. In this regard, three views on the relation between personal and subpersonal explanations are investigated: the autonomist, the functionalist, and the co-evolutionary perspective. I argue that, depending on which view of the relation between the personal and subpersonal is adopted, the PEM paradigm faces a dilemma: either its explanatory ambitions should be reduced to the subpersonal domain, or it cannot provide a satisfactory account of motivated reasoning as instantiated in self-deception.
Similar content being viewed by others
Data availability
Not applicable.
Code availability
Not applicable.
Notes
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for advising me to foreground this issue.
Formally, a generative model is a joint probability relating variables and state parameters. These variables and parameters are typically called “beliefs” because they represent different aspects of internal and external environments. However, given that they are probability distributions representing subconscious states, they should not be confused with beliefs construed as propositional attitudes (Dewhurst, 2017).
To keep things simple, I will refer to these motivational states as desires, which should be understood as an umbrella term for various pro-attitudes that play the functional role of goals or ground goals in commonsense psychological explanations (see, e.g. Smith, 1987).
Here the “inappropriateness” of weighting is determined with respect to how the optimal Bayesian agent would weigh the precisions of priors and incoming stimuli (see, e.g. Kuzmanovic & Rigoux, 2017). From the perspective of the PEM framework, belief updating always approximates optimality. The only way for the PEM framework to capture irrational or inadequate belief updating is in terms of the suboptimal generative models (see, e.g. Gadsby & Hohwy, 2021; Schwartenbeck et al., 2015). The significance of this claim will be discussed in Sects. 3.2 and 3.3.1.
In the only discussion so far on the relation between personal and subpersonal explanations within the context of PEM, Colombo and Fabry (2021) opt for the co-evolutionary model on independent grounds. However, in the present paper, my goal is not to adjudicate the plausibility of the different views of the relation between personal and subpersonal levels. Granted their initial plausibility, my goal is instead to investigate whether any of these views can be used to defend the PEM paradigm from the criticism that it cannot explain crucial features of self-deception.
Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me to be clearer about the purpose of this example.
References
Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Blackwell Publishing.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of psychology: A contemporary introduction. Routledge.
Chance, Z., & Norton, M. I. (2015). The what and why of self-deception. Current Opinion in Psychology, 6, 104–107. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.07.008
Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.
Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. MIT Press.
Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(03), 181–204. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12000477
Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (2020). Beyond desire? Agency, choice, and the predictive mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98, 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2019.1602661
Colombo, M. (2013). Constitutive relevance and the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Psychology, 26(4), 547–570. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2012.667623
Colombo, M. (2017). Social motivation in computational neuroscience: Or if brains are prediction machines, then the Humean theory of motivation is false. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), Routledge handbook of philosophy of the social mind (pp. 320–340). Routledge.
Colombo, M., & Fabry, R. E. (2021). Underlying delusion: Predictive processing, looping effects, and the personal/sub-personal distinction. Philosophical Psychology, 34(6), 829–855. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2021.1914828
Colombo, M., & Wright, C. (2017). Explanatory pluralism: An unrewarding prediction error for free energy theorists. Brain and Cognition, 112, 3–12.
Davidson, D. (2001). Essays on actions and events. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0199246270.001.0001
Dennett, D. C. (2010). Content and consciousness. Routledge.
Dewhurst, J. (2017). Folk psychology and the Bayesian brain. In T. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group.
Dewhurst, J. (2021). Folk psychological and neurocognitive ontologies. In F. Calzavarini & M. Viola (Eds.), Neural mechanisms (pp. 311–334). Springer.
Dołęga, K., & Dewhurst, J. E. (2021). Fame in the predictive brain: A deflationary approach to explaining consciousness in the prediction error minimization framework. Synthese, 198(8), 7781–7806. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02548-9
Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12014
Drayson, Z. (2014). The personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophy Compass, 9(5), 338–346. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12124
Fink, S. B., & Zednik, C. (2017). Meeting in the dark room: Bayesian rational analysis and hierarchical predictive coding. In T. K. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group.
Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00485230
Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn2787
Friston, K., FitzGerald, T., Rigoli, F., Schwartenbeck, P., & Pezzulo, G. (2017). Active inference: A process theory. Neural Computation, 29(1), 1–49. https://doi.org/10.1162/NECO_a_00912
Funkhouser, E. (2019). Self-deception. Routledge.
Gadsby, S., & Hohwy, J. (2021). Why use predictive processing to explain psychopathology? The case of anorexia nervosa. In D. Mendonça, M. Curado, & S. S. Gouveia (Eds.), The philosophy and science of predictive processing (pp. 209–226). Bloomsbury Academic.
Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford University Press.
Hohwy, J. (2020). New directions in predictive processing. Mind & Language, 35(2), 209–223. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12281
Hornsby, J. (1997). Simple mindedness: In defense of naive naturalism in the philosophy of mind. Harvard University Press.
Hornsby, J. (2000). Personal and sub-personal: A defence of Dennett’s early distinction. Philosophical Explorations, 3(1), 6–24. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869790008520978
Jefferson, A., Bortolotti, L., & Kuzmanovic, B. (2017). What is unrealistic optimism? Consciousness and Cognition, 50, 3–11. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.10.005
Kim, J. (1993). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. In J. Kim (Ed.), Supervenience and mind (pp. 309–335). Cambridge University Press.
Klein, C. (2018). What do predictive coders want? Synthese, 195(6), 2541–2557. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1250-6
Krstić, V. (2021). On the function of self-deception. European Journal of Philosophy, 29(4), 846–863. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12608
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108(3), 480–498.
Kuzmanovic, B., & Rigoux, L. (2017). Valence-dependent belief updating: Computational validation. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01087
Kuzmanovic, B., Rigoux, L., & Tittgemeyer, M. (2018). Influence of vMPFC on dMPFC predicts valence-guided belief formation. The Journal of Neuroscience, 38(37), 7996–8010. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0266-18.2018
Litwin, P., & Miłkowski, M. (2020). Unification by fiat: Arrested development of predictive processing. Cognitive Science. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12867
Marchi, F., & Newen, A. (2022). Self-deception in the predictive mind: Cognitive strategies and a challenge from motivation. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2021.2019693
Mathys, C. D. (2016). How could we get nosology from computation? In A. D. Redish & J. A. Gordon (Eds.), Computational psychiatry: New perspectives on mental illness (pp. 121–135). MIT Press.
Mathys, C. D., Daunizeau, J., Friston, K. J., & Stephan, K. E. (2011). A Bayesian foundation for individual learning under uncertainty. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2011.00039
McDowell, J. H. (1994). The content of perceptual experience. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44(175), 190. https://doi.org/10.2307/2219740
Mele, A. R. (2001). Self-deception unmasked. Princeton University Press.
Mele, A. R. (2006). Self-deception and delusions. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 2(1), 109–124.
Miller Tate, A. J. (2021). A predictive processing theory of motivation. Synthese, 198, 4493–4521. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02354-y
Parr, T., & Friston, K. J. (2021). Disconnection and diaschisis: Active inference in neuropsychology. In D. Mendonça, M. Curado, & S. S. Gouveia (Eds.), The philosophy and science of predictive processing (pp. 171–185). Bloomsbury Academic.
Pezzulo, G., Rigoli, F., & Friston, K. J. (2018). Hierarchical active inference: A theory of motivated control. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22(4), 294–306. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2018.01.009
Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9898-4
Powers, A. R., Mathys, C. D., & Corlett, P. R. (2017). Pavlovian conditioning-induced hallucinations result from overweighting of perceptual priors. Science, 357(6351), 596–600.
Ransom, M., Fazelpour, S., Markovic, J., Kryklywy, J., Thompson, E. T., & Todd, R. M. (2020). Affect-biased attention and predictive processing. Cognition, 203, 104370. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104370
Roskies, A., & Wood, C. (2017). Catching the prediction wave in brain science. Analysis, 77(4), 848–857. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anx083
Ross, D., & Spurrett, D. (2004). What to say to a skeptical metaphysician: A defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 603–627. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X04000147
Roth, M., & Cummins, R. (2018). Neuroscience, psychology, reduction, and functional analysis. In D. M. Kaplan (Ed.), Explanation and integration in mind and brain science. Oxford University Press.
Schwartenbeck, P., FitzGerald, T. H., Mathys, C., Dolan, R., Wurst, F., Kronbichler, M., & Friston, K. (2015). Optimal inference with suboptimal models: Addiction and active Bayesian inference. Medical Hypotheses, 84(2), 109–117.
Sharot, T. (2011). The optimism bias. Current Biology, 21(23), R941–R945. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2011.10.030
Sharot, T., & Garrett, N. (2016). Forming beliefs: Why valence matters. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(1), 25–33. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2015.11.002
Smith, M. (1987). The Humean theory of motivation. Mind, 96(381), 36–61.
Sprevak, M. (2021a). Predictive coding I: Introduction. TBC. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/19365
Sprevak, M. (2021b). Predictive coding II: The computational level. TBC. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/19366
Sterzer, P., Adams, R. A., Fletcher, P., Frith, C., Lawrie, S. M., Muckli, L., Petrovic, P., Uhlhaas, P., Voss, M., & Corlett, P. R. (2018). The predictive coding account of psychosis. Biological Psychiatry, 84(9), 634–643. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsych.2018.05.015
Sullivan-Bissett, E. (2022). Debunking doxastic transparency. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 18(1), (A3)5–24. https://doi.org/10.31820/ejap.18.1.3
Van Leeuwen, D. S. N. (2007). The product of self-deception. Erkenntnis, 67(3), 419–437. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9058-x
Wilkinson, S. (2014a). Accounting for the phenomenology and varieties of auditory verbal hallucination within a predictive processing framework. Consciousness and Cognition, 30, 142–155. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.09.002
Wilkinson, S. (2014b). Levels and kinds of explanation: Lessons from neuropsychiatry. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00373
Wilkinson, S. (2015). Dennett’s personal/subpersonal distinction in the light of cognitive neuropsychiatry. In C. Muñoz-Suárez & F. De Brigard (Eds.), Content and consciousness revisited (pp. 111–127). Springer.
Williams, D. (2020). Predictive coding and thought. Synthese, 197(4), 1749–1775. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1768-x
Williams, D. (2021). Epistemic irrationality in the Bayesian brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(4), 913–938. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz044
Yon, D., Heyes, C., & Press, C. (2020). Beliefs and desires in the predictive brain. Nature Communications, 11(1), 4404. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-020-18332-9
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for Synthese who provided critical and constructive comments that helped to improve the paper. Special thanks go to Luca Malatesti for reading and commenting on previous versions of the manuscript. Different versions of the paper were discussed and presented at numerous places. Most notable are the EPSA 2019 conference (Geneva) and Contemporary Philosophical Issues PhD 2021 (Rijeka). Thanks to Joe Dewhurst, Niccolò Aimone Pisano, Zdenka Brzović, and Matteo Colombo for giving valuable comments on those occasions. Part of the paper was written at the Institute of Philosophy of the University of Graz, where I was a visiting researcher supported by a scholarship from the Austrian Academy of Sciences (the JESH program). I would like to thank Norbert Paulo, Thomas Pölzler, and Lucas Meyer for supporting my grant application and for providing an ideal working environment in Graz.
Funding
This paper is an outcome of project Harm, intentions, and responsibility (HIRe) that is financed by the Croatian Science Foundation (grant number UIP- 2017-05-4308). Work on this paper is also supported by project KUBIM (University of Rijeka, grant Uniri-human-18-265).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
I declare no conflict of interest.
Ethical approval
Not applicable.
Consent to participate
Not applicable.
Consent for publication
Not applicable.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Jurjako, M. Can predictive processing explain self-deception?. Synthese 200, 303 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03797-6
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03797-6