Skip to main content
Log in

A metaphysical foundation for mathematical philosophy

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although mathematical philosophy is flourishing today, it remains subject to criticism, especially from non-analytical philosophers. The main concern is that even if formal tools serve to clarify reasoning, they themselves contribute nothing new or relevant to philosophy. We defend mathematical philosophy against such concerns here by appealing to its metaphysical foundations. Our thesis is that mathematical philosophy can be founded on the phenomenological theory of ideas as developed by Roman Ingarden. From this platonist perspective, the “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in philosophy”—to adapt Wigner’s phrase—is analogous to that of mathematical explanations in science. As success-criteria for mathematical philosophy, we propose that it should be correct, responsive, illuminating, promising, relevant, and adequate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are also diverse variants of realism: for instance, realism in respect of truth value, which is different from realism in ontology. A good example of the former, but not the latter, is Hellman’s (1989) modal structuralism: while he denies the existence of mathematical entities, he wants to preserve the notion of the truth of mathematical sentences (which must be defined in a different way than in terms of correspondence). What we have in mind in this paper is realism both in respect of truth value and in ontology: the truth of mathematical sentences is defined in terms of correspondence with an objectively existing realm of abstract objects.

  2. We wish to thank an anonymous referee for pressing us to be more explicit on these matters: in particular, as regards furnishing the motivation for engaging in such a thought experiment.

  3. Maddy, in a series of papers and a monograph (Maddy, 1989), defends her version of mathematical (set-theoretic) realism: in general terms, it is based on Quine’s influential indispensability argument, but according to Maddy this has some weaknesses, as it leaves out large fragments of set theory (which do not seem to play a role in applied mathematics). Rejecting Gödel’s notion of mathematical intuition, she aims to construct a naturalistic epistemology that will allow one to not only account for our knowledge of the truths of applied mathematics, but also to include set theory.

  4. These criteria are gradable—it is not a 0/1 matter whether some conception is promising or illuminating or not.

  5. Of the numerous examples in the literature we shall select just two, which we find especially persuasive. (1) The particular geometrical structure of honeycombs is explained by an optimization theorem to the effect that hexagonal tiling minimizes total perimeter length (Hales, 2001), where minimizing the amount of wax gives the bees an evolutionary advantage. (2) The Borsuk-Ulam theorem states that for any continuous function f from a sphere into R2, there will exist two antipodal points x, y, such that f(x) = f(y). This then provides a mathematical explanation of the fact that there are always two antipodal points on the surface of the Earth where temperature and pressure are both equal (Baker, 2005, 2009; Baker & Colyvan, 2011).

  6. The general idea of abstract explanation was introduced by Pettit and Jackson (2009), who discuss the example of a glass cracking after being filled with hot water: the inevitability of this scenario follows from general features of the system rather than from any particular sequence of micro-events. Pincock (2015) also discusses Plateau’s laws, stressing that although causally irrelevant to the explanandum, these abstract entities are nevertheless explanatorily relevant (see Pincock 2015, p. 857). In particular, “the mathematical entities central to the explanation are more abstract than the fact being explained” (Pincock, 2015, p. 864). From our point of view, it is important to stress that mathematics can identify some objective abstract dependence relations. It is not just a computational tool.

  7. “Explanations by constraint work not by describing the world’s causal relations, but rather by describing how the explanandum arises from certain facts (“constraints”) possessing some variety of necessity stronger than ordinary laws of nature possess” (Lange, 2017, p. 10).

  8. Gödel stresses the role of intuition in mathematics in many places—for instance, when discussing Carnap’s syntactic interpretation: “in whatever manner the syntactic rules are formulated, the power and usefulness of the mathematics resulting is proportional to the power of mathematical intuition necessary for their proof of admissibility… [I]t is clear that mathematical intuition cannot be replaced by conventions, but only by conventions plus mathematical intuition” (Gödel, 1953/9, p. 358).

  9. Though not in mathematics itself—if we agree with Monk (1976, p. 3) that something like 65% of working mathematicians are platonists.

  10. There are diverse variant of mathematical realism—see footnote 1.

  11. Regarding this, Detlefsen (2005) offers an excellent historical presentation.

  12. We are not asserting any strong dichotomy between mathematical philosophy and non-analytical philosophy (or, in particular, phenomenology). We should rather say that while mathematical philosophy is more similar in its form and methods to analytical philosophy, it might nevertheless be still more similar in substance to some strands of non-analytical philosophy. Moreover, when discussing these possible positions we have in mind their more radically orthodox variants. This is why we feel able to contrast them so starkly with each other.

  13. Mathematics does indeed identify fundamental modalities underlying physical phenomena, so one might well think of the relationship between mathematics and philosophy along similar lines.

  14. Several types of operation responsible for structuring mathematical cognition were distinguished by Mac Lane (1986, pp. 434–438).

  15. The grammar suggests that when we speak of ideas we are treating them as if they were objects. Nevertheless, it is not a grammatical object that is at stake in the present context. The term “object” is understood here in an ontological sense. Ingarden (2016, p. 75), in his ontology, distinguishes an individual object by defining it as follows: “An individual object, being what its nature makes it into (e.g. into a specific table or into a particular human being, say, I. Kant), contains a peculiar form which is best explicated as the immediately qualified subject of properties (or, more generally: of characteristics). In these properties it finds the consolidation [Ausgestaltung], and precisely therewith also the imprint [Ausprägung], of its self. It unfolds in them, as it were, and precisely therewith makes its imprint in them.”

  16. The issue of modes of existence was extensively researched by Ingarden (2013, pp. 95–161), but we lack the space to discuss it in detail here. In this article, we follow him in assuming that there are many ways of existing, where such ways (or modes of being) consist of some combination or other of existential moments. To illustrate this, we give here three pairings of such moments: autonomy—heteronomy; originality—derivativeness; self-sufficiency—non-self-sufficiency (Ingarden, 2013, p. 109ff). Existence, for Ingarden, is gradable: from weak intentional existence (e.g., works of art), through real existence (desks, stones and trees), and then ideal existence (mathematical objects, ideal qualities, ideas), to absolute existence (e.g., the God of philosophers). For a gentle introduction to Ingardenian ontology, we recommend Piwowarczyk (2020).

  17. Taking Kelly’s ideas from (1996), Schulte & Juhl (1996) point out certain similarities between topological and epistemological qualities. For instance, the Popperian notion of falsifiability is represented as one of the topological notions. (We shall not go into details here). Thanks to the procedure proposed by Kelly (1996), epistemology has been significantly enriched by new concepts, and a number of interesting and surprising results have been established—something that could hardly have been imagined before. There are many more examples of the phenomenon of “overlap” between topological and philosophical ideas in epistemology, philosophy of science and ontology Gruszczyński & Varzi, 2015; Kaczmarek, 2019; Skowron, Kaczmarek & Wójtowicz, unpublished).

  18. An interesting (but not very well-known) proposal is Vopěnka’s theory of semisets, where the notion of vagueness plays an important role. The conception is inspired by Husserl, and in particular by Husserl’s challenge to go “back to the things themselves”. Also, the notion of horizon has been an important source of inspiration. Interestingly, Vopěnka’s aim was not to put forward another formal version of set theory (and to investigate its metamathematical features within, for example, ZFC), but rather to treat it as a “naïve” theory, based on some new fundamental notions. For a thorough presentation, see Trlifajová (2022).

  19. Here, by “pre-closure algebra” is meant an algebra defined by three axioms: A1. x ≤ f(x), A2. f(f(x)) ≤ f(x) and A3. if x ≤ y, then f(x) ≤ f(y), where f is the operation of foundational closure which assigns objects their closures and ≤ is the relation of part to whole. If we add the axiom of additivity: A4. f(xy) = f(x) ∪ f(y), we obtain the so-called “closure algebra” (see Fine 1995, p. 475–485).

  20. The concept of object is understood here in a broad sense: for example, the brightness of a color is an object.

  21. Here we focus on work dealing with the probability of conditionals, not even mentioning the vast subject that is “the logic of conditionals”. What are the appropriate axioms and rules of inference? See, for instance, Leitgeb (2012) for a comprehensive formal account of a probabilistic semantics that also addresses such logical aspects. We, on the other hand, focus on non-logical investigations here.

  22. Consider the classic “wet match” example: If the match is wet, then it will light if you strike it. Assume that the probabilities are as follows (Kaufmann, 2005, p. 206): (a) that the match is wet = 0.1; (b) that you strike it = 0.5; (c) that it lights given that you strike it and it is dry = 0.9; (d) that it lights given that you strike it and it is wet = 0.1. Moreover, striking the match is independent of its wetness. Kaufmann’s formula gives a result of 0.46, which is counterintuitive, as we would expect the probability to be 0.1.

  23. The probabilistic version of the Import-Export Principle for conditionals states that the probabilities of α→(β→γ) and (α∧β)→γ are the same.

  24. Informally speaking, Markov chain theory deals with random events, which unfold in time and are memoryless—like tossing a coin many times. The coin does not remember its history, and the (n + 1)st result is independent from what was happening before. A classic example is the Gambler’s Ruin Problem: two players toss a coin (it might be fair or not), and at every turn the loser gives one penny to the winner. The game lasts until one of the players is ruined, i.e. has no pennies left. Markov chain theory allows one to answer such questions as “What is the chance that the gambler will be ruined?”, “What is the average time of the game?”, etc. One of the advantages of the theory is that it furnishes computationally simple methods for dealing with such problems.

  25. Once we have set up a formal model for conditionals, we will inevitably find ourselves postulating truth conditions for these that are of a different nature than for factual sentences. The existence of such truth conditions is another matter—but if we do postulate them, they will have to be very different.

  26. Probability is a classic example of a mathematical explication of the common-sense notion of chance; see Carnap (1950), or Brun (2016) for a still more contemporary treatment. Of course, the problem of whether some concept is originally philosophical, or has perhaps been “imported” into philosophical discussions from other sciences, is a highly delicate one: just what is the status of a notion such as propensity?

  27. The famous quotation from Carnap runs as follows: “In logic, there are no morals. Everyone is at liberty to build up his own logic, i.e., his own form of language, as he wishes. All that is required of him is that, if he wishes to discuss it, he must state his methods clearly, and give syntactical rules instead of philosophical arguments” (Carnap, 1937, § 17). So there are no limitations, apart from pragmatic and logical ones. Our proposal is to some extent similar—but we acknowledge that there are some objective limitations apart from logical ones when setting up formal systems (provided we do not want to just play a conceptual game). This situation exactly recalls that of the working mathematician who, on the one hand, is free to adopt any (consistent) set of premises, axioms and conventions, but, on the other, strives for natural concepts, reliable assumptions, etc.

  28. We have borrowed the first five of these terms from Mac Lane (1986, pp. 440–446). Although Mac Lane refers to the development of mathematics and not philosophy, these criteria, with minor changes and additions, can also be applied to philosophy (and not only of a mathematical kind). We shall not indicate here exactly the points where the content of a given criterion has been altered, and where we have literally transferred it, as this would require a separate treatment extraneous to the goals of the present article.

  29. “Once the axioms of a system are set, all the statements of the system are either demonstrable, refutable, or (thanks to Gödel) undecidable. No collusion, no political influence, no second thoughts can alter the fact of the matter that the theorem can be proved. Given the straightforward definition of a finite simple group, the existence of the ‘monster’ is ineluctable” (Mac Lane, 1986, p. 442).

  30. There is an ongoing discussion concerning the nature of mathematical proofs. The proofs known from mathematical practice are not formalized—however, they are rigorous. This issue was briefly addressed by us in section 2; see Hamami (2018) for an extensive discussion.

  31. Wang made the following comment on Kurt Gödel: “In recent years set theory has become more and more specialized and removed from generally accessible conceptual problems. If G were young today, he would be unlikely to choose to specialize in set theory. He wants philosophy to be ‘precise but not technical’ and believes that highly specialized knowledge is not relevant to basic conceptual problems” (Wang, 1987, 208). This is a danger for MP—that its tools become so complex that they turn into the object of study themselves (in place of the philosophical problems they were intended to solve).

  32. Even if we are 99.999% sure that we will win some game, we would not pay $1,000 to participate in it if, on average, it takes 100 billion years to be completed (i.e. if this is the expected “absorption time” for the process). Thus, if this notion is to really be of practical value, we must have the feeling that it is possible to stop the process soon. (We thank an anonymous referee for this observation).

  33. Marquise (2020) describes how a categorical understanding of logic points to the rich mathematical structures contained in logic itself.

  34. Mac Lane (1939), in a review of Benedict Bornstein’s philosophically erudite book Geometrical Logic. The Structures of Thought and Space, without investigating the philosophical purpose and metaphysical attitude of its author, characterizes the latter’s work as a “grandiloquent, naive, and confused” endeavor. Mathematical philosophers are often cast as guilty of naivety.

  35. Let us take the example mentioned above, of Kelly’s topological epistemology, and ask why it is that, in the language of models, it is the topological model that fits the epistemological problems. It is because verifiability and topological openness turn out to be the same set of ideal qualities (providing that Kelly’s intuitings are adequate). These sets of ideal qualities are then made concrete in the contents of certain philosophical and mathematical ideas, which turn out to be the very same ideas! For details, we refer the reader to the book by Kelly (1996), and to the accessible discussion of Kelly’s results in Schulte & Juhl (1996).

  36. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out this problem. Modeling is not a search for complete and perfect adequacy—if it were, there would be no room left for new insights.

References

  • Aristotle (1991). Metaphysics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton University Press

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611–633

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A., & Colyvan, A. (2011). Indexing and mathematical explanation. Philosophia Mathematica, 19, 232–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. Oxford University Press

  • Brun, G. (2016). Explication as a method of conceptual re-engineering. Erkenntnis, 81(6), 1211–1241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1937). The logical syntax of language. London: Kegan Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. University of Chicago Press/Routledge and Kegan Paul

  • Casari, E. (2000). On Husserl’s theory of wholes and parts. History and Philosophy of Logic, 21(1), 1–43. https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340050044628

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, P. J., Hersh, R., & Marchisotto, E. A. (2012). The mathematical experience, study edition. Birkhäuser Boston. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-8176-8295-8

  • Detlefsen, M. (2005). Formalism. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 236–317). Oxford University Press

  • Eilenberg, S., & Mac Lane, S. (1945). General theory of natural equivalences. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 58, 231–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Part-whole. In B. Smith & D. W. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Husserl (Cambridge companions to philosophy) (pp. 463–486). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521430232.011

  • Fleck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact. The University of Chicago Press. (Originally published in German, 1935)

  • Frege, G. Sources of Knowledge of Mathematics and Natural Sciences, transl., & Long, P. (1979). & R. White. In Gottlob Frege: Posthumous writings (pp. 267–74). Chicago: University of Chicago Press

  • Gödel, K. (1953/9). Is mathematics a syntax of language? In S. Feferman (Ed.), Kurt Gödel: Collected works, vol. III (pp. 334–363). Oxford University Press

  • Gödel, K. (1964). What is Cantor’s Continuum Problem?. In P. Benacerraf, & H. Putnam (Eds.), Philosophy of mathematics: Selected readings (pp. 258–273). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall

    Google Scholar 

  • Greif, H. (2021). Exploring minds. Modes of modelling and simulation in artificial intelligence. Perspectives on Science, 29(4), 409–435. https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruszczyński, R., & Varzi, A. (2015). Mereology then and now. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 24(4), 409–427. https://doi.org/10.12775/LLP.2015.024

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hales, T. C. (2001). The honeycomb conjecture. Discrete and Computational Geometry, 25, 1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallett, M. (1984). Cantorian set theory and limitation of size (Oxford logic guides 10). Oxford: Clarendon Press

  • Hamami, Y. (2018). Mathematical inference and logical inference. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 11(4), 665–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (1929). Mathematical proof. Mind, 38, 1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Llored, J. P. (2011). Mereologies as the grammars of chemical discourses. Foundations of Chemistry, 13, 63–76. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-011-9103-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartimo, M. H. (2007). Towards completeness: Husserl on theories of manifolds 1890–1901. Synthese, 156, 281–310. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-0008-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartimo, M. H. (Ed.). (2010). (Ed.) Phenomenology and mathematics (Phaenomenologica 195). Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3729-9

  • Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without Numbers. Oxford: Clarendon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations,vol. II, trans. J. N. Findlay, ed. D. Moran. Routledge

  • Hutchins, E. (2012). Concepts in practice as sources of order. Mind Culture and Activity, 19(3), 314–323. https://doi.org/10.1080/10749039.2012.694006

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1971). U podstaw teorii poznania (Foundations of the theory of knowledge), PWN

  • Ingarden, R. (2013). Controversy over the existence of the world, vol. I, trans. A. Szylewicz. Peter Lang

  • Ingarden, R. (2016). Controversy over the existence of the world, vol. II, trans. A. Szylewicz. Peter Lang

  • Kaczmarek, J. (2019). Ontology in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: A Topological Approach. In G. M. Mras, P. Weingartner & B. Ritter (Eds.) Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics: Proceedings of the 41st International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter, pp. 397–414. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110657883-024

  • Kaufmann, S. (2004). Conditioning against the grain: Abduction and indicative conditionals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33(6), 583–606

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, S. (2005). Conditional predictions: A probabilistic account. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(2), 181–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, S. (2009). Conditionals right and left: Probabilities for the whole family. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38, 1–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, S. (2015). Conditionals, conditional probability, and conditionalization. In H. Zeevat, & H. C. Schmitz (Eds.), Bayesian natural language semantics and pragmatics (pp. 71–94). Springer

  • Kelly, K. (1996). The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Oxford University Press

  • Król, Z. (2015). Platonism and the development of mathematics. Infinity and geometry. Wydawnictwo Instytutu Filozofii i Socjologii PAN

  • Lange, M. (2017). Because without Cause. Non-Causal Explanations in Science and Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2011). Logic in general philosophy of science: Old things and new things. Synthese, 179, 339–350. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9776-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2012). A probabilistic semantics for conditionals. Parts A and B. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(1), 26–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2013). Scientific philosophy, mathematical philosophy, and all that. Metaphilosophy, 44, 267–275. https://doi.org/10.1111/meta.12029

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical Papers, vol. II (pp. 133–156). Oxford University Press

  • Mac Lane, S. (1939). Review of Benedykt Bornstein, Geometrical logic. The structures of thought and space (Bibliotheca Universitatis Liberae Polonae, ser. B, no. 8 (31), Wolna Wszechnica Polska, 1939). The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 4(3), 133–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S. (1983). The health of mathematics. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 5, 53–56. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03026510

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S. (1986). Mathematics: Form and function. Springer

  • Maddy, P. (1990). Realism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J. P. (2020). Abstract logical structuralism. Philosophical Problems in Science (Zagadnienia Filozoficzne w Nauce) 69 (2020), 67–110. https://zfn.edu.pl/index.php/zfn/article/view/518/517

  • McGee, V. (1989). Conditional probabilities and compounds of conditionals. Philosophical Review, 48(4), 485–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (1998). Field’s programme: Some interference. Analysis, 58(2), 63–71. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/58.2.63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monk, J. D. (1976). Mathematical logic. Springer New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4684-9452-5

  • Mormann, T. (2009). Updating classical mereology. In C. Glymour, W. Wang, & D. Westerstahl (Eds.), Proceedings of the 13th international conference on logic, methodology and philosophy of science, Beijing 2007 (pp. 326–343). King’s College Publications

  • Mormann, T. (2013). Topology as an issue for history of philosophy of science. InH. Andersen, D. Dieks, W. Gonzalez, T. Uebel, & G. Wheeler (Eds.), New challenges to philosophy of science (The philosophy of science in a European perspective, Vol 4). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5845-2_34

  • Null, G. T. (1983). A first-order axiom system for non-universal part-whole and foundation relations. In L. Embree (Ed.), Essays in Memory of Aron Gurwitsch (pp. 463–483). Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology

  • Null, G. T., & Blecksmith, R. (1991). Matrix representation of Husserl’s part-whole-foundation theory. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 32(1), 87–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990). Program explanation: a general perspective. Analysis, 50(2), 107–117. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/50.2.107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietruszczak, A. (2020). Foundations of the theory of parthood. A study of mereology. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-36533-2

  • Pincock, C. (2015). Abstract explanations in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 857–882. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axu016

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piwowarczyk, M. (2020). Roman Ingarden’s early theory of the object. In W. Płotka & P. Eldridge (Eds.), Early phenomenology in Central and Eastern Europe. Contributions to phenomenology (In cooperation with the Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology), vol. 113 (pp. 111–126). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-39623-7_7

  • Pratt-Hartmann, I. (2007). First-order mereotopology. In M. Aiello, I. Pratt-Hartmann, & J. van Benthem (Eds.), Handbook of Spatial Logics (pp. 13–97). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5587-4_2

  • Rota, G. C. (1991). Mathematics and the task of phenomenology. In T. M. Seebohm, D. Føllesdal, & J. N. Mohanty (Eds.), Phenomenology and the formal sciences. Contributions to phenomenology (In cooperation with the Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology), vol. 8 (pp. 133–138). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2580-2_9

  • Rota, G. C. (1992). Husserl. In M. Kac, G-C. Rota, & J., Schwartz (Eds.), Discrete thoughts: Essays on mathematics, science, and philosophy (2nd edition, corrected and edited by P. Renz). Birkhäuser

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1966). The world as will and representation, vol. 1, trans. by E. F. J. Payne. Dover

  • Schulte, O., & Juhl, C. (1996). Topology as epistemology. The Monist, 79, 141–147. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist19967916

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (2003). Parts: A study in ontology. Oxford University Press

  • Skowron, B. (2015). Using mathematical modeling as an example of qualitative reasoning in metaphysics: A note on a defense of the theory of ideas. Annals of Computer Science and Information Systems, 7, 65–68. https://doi.org/10.15439/978-83-60810-78-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skowron, B. (2017). Mereotopology. In H. Burkhardt, J. Seibt, G. Imaguire, & S. Gerogiorgakis (Eds.), Handbook of Mereology (pp. 354–361). Philosophia

  • Skowron, B., & Wójtowicz, K. (2021). Throwing spatial light: On topological explanation in Gestalt psychology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 537–558. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09691-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skowron, B., Bigaj, T., Chrudzimski, A., Głowala, M., Król, Z., Kuś, M., et al. (2019). An assessment of contemporary Polish ontology. In B. Skowron (Ed.), Contemporary Polish ontology. De Gruyter. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110669411-015

  • Skowron, B., Wójtowicz, K., & Kaczmarek, J. (manuscript). Towards a Topological Philosophy

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A Theory of Conditionals. Studies in logical theory American Philosophical Quarterly monograph, 2, 98–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1970). Probability and conditionals. Philosophy of Science, 37(1), 64–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R., & Thomason, R. H. (1970). A semantic analysis of conditional logic. Theoria, 36(1), 23–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thom, R. (1971). “Modern” mathematics: An educational and philosophic error? American Scientist, 59(6), 695–699

    Google Scholar 

  • Tieszen, R. (1992). Kurt Gödel and phenomenology. Philosophy of Science, 59, 176–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tieszen, R. (1995). Mathematics. In B. Smith, & D. W. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy) (pp. 438–462). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521430232.010

  • Tieszen, R. (1998). Gödel’s path from the incompleteness theorems (1931) to phenomenology (1961), The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 4, 181–203

  • Tieszen, R. (2005). Phenomenology, logic, and the philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge University Press

  • Trlifajová, K. (2022). Infinity and continuum in the alternative set theory. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 2–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00429-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski, K. (1979). Symbolomania and pragmatophobia. In J. Pelc (Ed.), Semiotics in Poland 1984–1969. Synthese Library (Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science), vol. 119. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9777-6_2

  • Wang, H. (1987). Reflections on Kurt Gödel. MIT Press

  • Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2017). Model-building in philosophy. In R. Blackford, & D. Broderick (Eds.), Philosophy’s future: The problem of philosophical progress. Wiley-Blackwell

  • Wójtowicz, A., & Wójtowicz, K. (2021). A stochastic graphs semantics for conditionals. Erkenntnis, 86, 1071–1105. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00144-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wójtowicz, A., & Wójtowicz, K. (2022). A graph model for probabilities of nested conditionals. Linguistics and Philosophy, 45, 511–558. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-021-09324-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals. In W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Foundations of probability theory, statistical inference, and statistical theories of science (The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 1) (pp. 261–308). D. Reidel

  • Yablo, S. (2002). Abstract objects: A case study. Nous, 36(s1), 220–240. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0068.36.s1.7

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The preparation of this paper was supported by the National Science Center (Poland), grant no. 2016/21/B/HS1/01955 (Principal Investigator: Krzysztof Wójtowicz). The authors would like to thank (in alphabetical order) Samuel Fletcher, Hajo Greif, Carl Humphries, Zbigniew Król, Józef Lubacz, Thomas Mormann, Paula Quinon, Antonio Vassallo, and Frank Zenker for their comments. The theses of the paper were presented at a seminar of the International Center for Formal Ontology (Faculty of Administration and Social Sciences, Warsaw University of Technology), and we would like to thank the participants for the lively discussion that ensued there. We are also grateful to Carl Humphries for proofreading this text, and to three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments. The authors accept sole responsibility, of course, for all and any shortcomings in the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bartłomiej Skowron.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wójtowicz, K., Skowron, B. A metaphysical foundation for mathematical philosophy. Synthese 200, 299 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03760-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03760-5

Keywords

Navigation