Skip to main content
Log in

The affective and normative intentionality of skilled performance: a radical embodied approach

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we argue that the intentionality at play in skilled performance is not only inherently normative but also inherently affective. We take a radically embodied approach to the mind in which we conceive of cognitive agents as sensorimotor systems moved to maintain their biological and sociocultural identity, whose perception is direct and occurs in terms of affordances. Within this framework, we define skilled performance as the enactment of action and perception patterns in which the agent is intentionally oriented towards specific features in the environment. We propose that (i) skillful intentionality is guided by normative constraints involving the material and social conditions of the agent but is ultimately determined by the intrinsic purpose of maintaining the agent’s identity, and (ii) skilled intentionality is inherently affective because it is a specific occurrence arising from a general sense of care to maintain one’s identity which is realized by orienting oneself towards the right aspects of the environment in the right way. Skilled performance thus requires agents to establish a normative and affective intentionality towards aspects of their material environment. We show that, since sociocultural practices shape human identities, sociocultural practices play a crucial role in shaping human intentionality of skilled performance both in their normative and affective dimensions. Maintaining a human identity, we argue, amounts to routinely carrying out activities that form a historical pattern which is shared with and recognized by others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This applies not only to humans, but to any form of life whose patterns of interaction are relatively uncoupled from the metabolic needs of the organism.

  2. It seems that not all sensorimotor schemes need to be frequently enacted in order to be maintained. For example, schemes that support activities that once were frequently enacted, such as riding a bicycle or dancing, might not disappear after years of not enacting them (Di Paolo et al., 2017). The variation between schemes in regard their durability through time is an open question.

References

  • Baggs, E., & Chemero, A. (2018). Radical embodiment in two directions. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02020-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baggs, E., Raja, V., & Anderson, M. L. (2020). Extended skill learning. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01956

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., Chemero, A., & Rietveld, E. (2019). General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for ‘higher’ cognition. Synthese, 196(12), 5231–5251. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1716-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2013). The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. E. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Cuffari, E. C., & De Jaegher, H. (2018). Linguistic bodies: The continuity between life and language. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dotov, D., Nie, L., Wojcik, K., Jinks, A., Yu, X., & Chemero, A. (2017). Cognitive and movement measures reflect the transition to presence-at-hand. New Ideas in Psychology, 45, 1–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002). Intelligence without representation–Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation The relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elias, J. Z. (2017). 13 the extent of our abilities: The presence, salience, and sociality of affordances. Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World, 245.

  • Feiten, T. E. (2020). Mind after Uexküll: A foray into the worlds of ecological psychologists and enactivists. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2018). Ecology of the brain: The phenomenology and biology of the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., Hutto, D., Ilundain-Agurruza, J., Kirchhoff, M., Miyahara, K., & Robertson, I. (2019). Minds in skilled performance: From phenomenology to cognitive explanations. Annual Review of the Phenomenological Association of Japan, 35, 1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Gastelum, M. (2020). Scale matters: Temporality in the perception of affordances. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 1188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (2009). Emotions as evaluative feelings. Emotion Review, 1(3), 248–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano, M. (2019). The philosophy of affordances. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, B. H. (2007). Values define fields: The intentional dynamics of driving, carrying, leading, negotiating, and conversing. Ecological Psychology, 19(2), 153–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (2011). Being alive: Essays on movement, knowledge and description. Taylor & Francis.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012 [1962]). Phenomenology of perception (D. Landes, Trans.). Routledge.

  • Michaels, C. F., & Carello, C. (1981). Direct perception. Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1995). Pushmi-pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mojica, L. (2020). Reclaiming meaning, reclaiming normativity. Constructivist, Foundations, 15(3), 216–218

    Google Scholar 

  • Mojica, L., & Froese, T. (2019). On the spatiotemporal extensiveness of sense-making: ultrafast cognition and the historicity of normativity. Synthese, 1–14.

  • Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological autonomy: A philosphical and theoretical enquiry. (Vol. 12)Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E., & Mylopoulos, M. (2020). Beyond automaticity: The psychological complexity of skill. Topoi, 1–14.

  • Pellegrini, A. D., Dupuis, D., & Smith, P. K. (2007). Play in evolution and development. Developmental Review, 27(2), 261–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Port, R. F., & Van Gelder, T. (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2014.958035

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, T. (1996). Social practices: A Wittgensteinian approach to human activity and the social. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). Phenomenology and agency: Methodological and theoretical issues in Strawson’s ‘The Self.’ Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(4), 48–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. (2008). Affective intentionality and the feeling body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7(4), 429–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. (2012). Emotional rationality and feelings of being. Feelings of being alive, 8, 55

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J., & Wüschner, P. (2014). Emotion and agency. Emotion and Value, 212–228.

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. Noûs, 51(4), 713–726. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szokolszky, A., Read, C., Palatinus, Z., & Palatinus, K. (2019). Ecological approaches to perceptual learning: Learning to perceive and perceiving as learning. Adaptive Behavior, 27(6), 363–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., Shaw, R. E., Reed, E. S., & Mace, W. M. (1981). Ecological laws of perceiving and acting: In reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn (1981). Cognition, 9(3), 237–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In Organism and the origins of self (pp. 79–107): Springer.

  • von Uexküll, J. (1926). Theoretical biology.

  • von Uexküll, J. (1957). A stroll through the worlds of animals and men, instinctive behavior. (pp. 5–80). Int. Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020368120174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Laura Mojica acknowledges support by the Okinawa Institute of Science and Technology (OIST) and by a scholarship granted by the Mexican Council for Science and Technology (Consejo Nacional de Ciencia y Tecnología, CONACyT). Melina Gastelum acknowledges support by the Mexican Council for Science and Technology (Consejo Nacional de Ciencia y Tecnología, CONACyT) and to the support of the PAPIIT IN 402018 “Cognición, artefactualidad y representación en la ciencia,” directed by Dr. Sergio Martínez at UNAM. Both authors thank Katsunori Miyahara and the anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Melina Gastelum Vargas.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the topical collection on Minds in Skilled Performance, edited by Katsunori Miyahara, Ian Robertson and Michael Kirchhoff.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mojica, L., Gastelum Vargas, M. The affective and normative intentionality of skilled performance: a radical embodied approach. Synthese 199, 8205–8230 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03159-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03159-8

Keywords

Navigation