Skip to main content
Log in

Fighting about frequency

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 18 May 2021

This article has been updated

Abstract

Scientific disputes about how often different processes or patterns occur are relative frequency controversies. These controversies occur across the sciences. In some areas—especially biology—they are even the dominant mode of dispute. Yet they depart from the standard picture of what a scientific controversy is like. In fact, standard philosophical accounts of scientific controversies suggest that relative frequency controversies are irrational or lacking in epistemic value. This is because standard philosophical accounts of scientific controversies often assume that in order to be rational, a scientific controversy must (a) reach a resolution and (b) be about a scientifically interesting question. Relative frequency controversies rarely reach a resolution, however, and some scientists and philosophers are skeptical that these controversies center on scientifically interesting questions. In this paper, I provide a novel account of the epistemic contribution that relative frequency controversies make to science. I show that these controversies are rational in the sense of furthering the epistemic aims of the scientific communities in which they occur. They do this despite rarely reaching a resolution, and independent of whether the controversies are about scientifically interesting questions. This means that assumptions (a) and (b) about what is required for a controversy to be rational are wrong. Controversies do not need to reach a resolution in order to be rational. And they do not need to be about anything scientifically interesting in order to make valuable epistemic contributions to science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. This difference is nicely captured in Godfrey-Smith’s (2001) distinction between empirical adaptationism (an issue of frequency) and explanatory adaptationism (an issue of significance).

  2. Here and throughout the paper, I use the term “theory” in an informal sense—often synonymously with “hypothesis” or “mechanism.”

  3. Beatty (1997) defines the relative significance of a scientific theory as “roughly the proportion of phenomena within the domain that the theory correctly describes” (p. S432). He does not explicitly define the term “scientific controversy.” My own understanding of “scientific controversy” follows Ernest McMullin’s: “a publicly and persistently maintained dispute…concerned with a matter of belief…determinable by scientific means” (1987, p. 51).

  4. Though not the paradigmatic type of case, controversies about the relative roles of different causal factors in producing single-event phenomena (e.g. the extinction of dinosaurs) are, if not relative frequency controversies, quite similar to them in terms of their structure and dynamics.

  5. Though not uncontroversial: see Kelly (2003).

  6. There is a long history of philosophical debate on this point. I am particularly persuaded by Angela Potochnik’s (2015) defense of the idea that science’s epistemic aims are subject to change and expansion.

  7. Similar observations from other philosophers can be found in Millstein (2007), Skipper (2002, 2009) and Plutynski (2005). For an example of a relative frequency controversy that looks like it is in the process of being abandoned, see Bird et al.’s analysis of the controversy over sympatric speciation (2012, p. 176), as well as Via (2001) and Jiggins (2006).

  8. That relative frequency controversies often go unresolved is basically a consensus position in the scientific and philosophical literature on these controversies. Still, one might disagree with this claim, either because no one is in a position to report the actual proportion of resolved to unresolved controversies, or because eliminating some possible answers to the original relative frequency question seems like resolution of a sort. If you are not persuaded that these controversies are often unresolved, the important point for my argument is that their being resolved is independent of their being rational, as I discuss in Sect. 5.

  9. It's also a relative frequency controversy in its own right! For a discussion, see (Turner 2015).

  10. I intend the following discussion to be neutral among competing characterizations of scientific explanation.

  11. They can also be a mechanism by which new processes which can produce the phenomenon of interest are discovered. Mary Jane West-Eberhard (1984) did not propose the sensory bias model for sexual selection (in which mating preferences evolve from pre-existing sensory preferences) until 1984, years into the ongoing debate about good genes versus arbitrary choice, and peripatric and parapatric speciation were not recognized as mechanisms until the sympatric vs. allopatric controversy was well underway.

  12. The tendency to start with what Adrian Currie (2019) calls simple, “one-shot” hypotheses is it not necessarily an epistemic failing; rather, it could be an epistemically valuable strategic move that put scientists in a better position to investigate complex combinations of causal factors farther down the line.

  13. See Jiggins (2006) for a similar analysis of the development of the sympatric speciation controversy.

  14. Though it would be a mistake to take any of my claims in this paper as establishing the rationality of other kinds of unresolved, polarizing controversies! Whether the considerations that establish the rationality of relative frequency controversies apply to other kinds of cases would have to be investigated separately.

References

  • Beatty, J. (1997). Why do biologists argue like they do? Philosophy of Science, 64, S432–S443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, C. E., Fernandez-Silva, I., Skillings, D. J., & Toonen, R. J. (2012). Sympatric speciation in the post ‘Modern Synthesis’ era of evolutionary biology. Evolutionary Biology, 39(2), 158–180. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-012-9183-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012). Is water H2O?: Evidence, realism and pluralism. . Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, A. (2019). Simplicity, one-shot hypotheses and paleobiological explanation. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 41(1), 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1986). The blind watchmaker. Norton. Retrieved from http://www.bcin.ca/Interface/openbcin.cgi?submit=submit&Chinkey=121606

  • Diaconis, P., Holmes, S., & Montgomery, R. (2007). Dynamical bias in the coin toss. SIAM Review, 49(2), 211–235. https://doi.org/10.1137/S0036144504446436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, M. (2006). From Mendel to molecules: a brief history of evolutionary genetics.

  • Feder, J. L., Chilcote, C. A., & Bush, G. L. (1988). Genetic differentiation between sympatric host races of the apple maggot fly Rhagoletis pomonella. Nature, 336(6194), 61–64. https://doi.org/10.1038/336061a0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2006). Reasonable religious disagreements. In L. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without gods: Meditations on atheism and the secular life.( pp. 194–214). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1987). The theory of epistemic rationality. . Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. (2009). Spandrels and a pervasive problem of evidence. Biology and Philosophy, 24(2), 247–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forsgård, R. A. (2019). Lactose digestion in humans: intestinal lactase appears to be constitutive whereas the colonic microbiome is adaptable. The American Journal of Clinical Nutrition, 110(2), 273–279. https://doi.org/10.1093/ajcn/nqz104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foulger, G. R. (2010). Plates versus Plumes: A geological controversy. (1st ed.). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freudenthal, G. (2000). A rational controversy over compounding forces. (p. 125). Philosophical and historical perspectives.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1989). Scientific rationality as instrumental rationality. Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 20(3), 377–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2001). Three kinds of adaptationism. In S. H. Orzack & E. Sober (Eds.), Adaptationism and Optimality. (pp. 335–357). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1980). Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging? Paleobiology, 6(1), 119–130. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0094837300012549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, B. R., & Grant, P. R. (2003). What Darwin’s finches can teach us about the evolutionary origin and regulation of biodiversity. BioScience, 53(10), 965–975.

    Google Scholar 

  • He, T., Venema, K., Priebe, M. G., Welling, G. W., Brummer, R. J., & Vonk, R. J. (2008). The role of colonic metabolism in lactose intolerance. European Journal of Clinical Investigation, 38(8), 541–547.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. (1999). The neutralist, the fly and the selectionist. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 14(1), 35–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. (2017). The evolutionary implications of epigenetic inheritance. Interface Focus, 7(5), 20160135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiggins, C. D. (2006). Sympatric speciation: Why the controversy? Current Biology: CB, 16(9), R333-334. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2006.03.077.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. (2007). Natural history as stamp collecting: A brief history. Archives of Natural History, 34(2), 244–258. https://doi.org/10.3366/anh.2007.34.2.244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: A critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 612–640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2010). Peer Disagreement and Higher Order Evidence. In R. Feldman & T. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2000). Patterns of scientific controversies. In P. K. Machamer, M. Pera, & A. Baltas (Eds.), Scientific Controversies: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1992). The naturalists return. The Philosophical Review, 101(1), 53–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labor. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(1), 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lander, E. S. (2016). The heroes of CRISPR. Cell, 164(1–2), 18–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond positivism and relativism: Theory, method, and evidence. . Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebert, A., López, S., Jones, B. L., Montalva, N., Gerbault, P., Lau, W., Thomas, M. G., Bradman, N., Maniatis, N., & Swallow, D. M. (2017). World-wide distributions of lactase persistence alleles and the complex effects of recombination and selection. Human genetics, 136(11–12), 1445–1453. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00439-017-1847-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A., & Gould, S. J. (1993). Species selection on variability. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 90(2), 595–599. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.90.2.595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matheson, J. (2015). The epistemic significance of disagreement. . Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo-Wilson, C., Zollman, K. J., & Danks, D. (2011). The independence thesis: When individual and social epistemology diverge. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 653–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1947). Ecological factors in speciation. Evolution, 1(4), 263–288. https://doi.org/10.2307/2405327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1987). Scientific controversy and its termination. In H. T. Engelhardt & A. L. Caplan (Eds.), Scientific Controversies: Case Studies in the Resolution and Closure of Disputes in Science and Technology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. L. (2007). Hsp90-induced evolution: Adaptationist, neutralist, and developmentalist scenarios. Biological Theory, 2(4), 376–386. https://doi.org/10.1162/biot.2007.2.4.376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, J. M., & Hellmann, J. J. (2008). An assessment of invasion risk from assisted migration. Conservation Biology, 22(3), 562–567. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1523-1739.2008.00952.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., Murren, C. J., & Schlichting, C. D. (2006). Phenotypic plasticity and evolution by genetic assimilation. Journal of Experimental Biology, 209(12), 2362–2367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Müller, G. B. (Eds.). (2010). Evolution, the extended synthesis. . The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plutynski, A. (2005). Explanatory unification and the early synthesis. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56(3), 595–609. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axi124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2017). Idealization and the Aims of Science. . University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2015). Causal patterns and adequate explanations. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1163–1182. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0342-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2010). Explanatory independence and epistemic interdependence: A case study of the optimality approach. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(1), 213–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W. B. (1992). The R. A. Fisher—Sewall Wright Controversy in the founders of evolutionary genetics. . Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2000). The theory of punctuated equilibria. In P. K. Machamer, M. Pera, & A. Baltas (Eds.), Scientific Controversies: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savolainen, V., Anstett, M.-C., Lexer, C., Hutton, I., Clarkson, J. J., Norup, M. V., & Baker, W. J. (2006). Sympatric speciation in palms on an oceanic island. Nature, 441(7090), 210–213. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature04566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R. A. (2002). The persistence of the R.A. Fisher-Sewall Wright controversy. Biology and Philosophy, 17(3), 341–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R. A. (2009). Revisiting the fisher-wright controversy. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, 99(1), 299–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (1992). Scientific rationality and human reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 59(3), 439–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2010). Epistemic values and the argument from inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 77(1), 14–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2003). The role of the priority rule in science. The Journal of philosophy, 100(2), 55–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2015). Historical contingency and the explanation of evolutionary trends in explanation in biology. . Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1996). It is wrong, always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything, upon insufficient evidence. In J. Jordan & D. Howard-Snyder (Eds.), Faith, Freedom, and Rationality. (pp. 137–154). Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Via, S. (2001). Sympatric speciation in animals: The ugly duckling grows up. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 16(7), 381–390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (1984). Sexual selection, competitive communication and species-specific signals in insects. In T. Lewis (Ed.), Insect Communication. (pp. 283–324). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. (2010). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 17.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Colin Allen, Anjan Chakravartty, Michael Dietrich, Edouard Machery, Billy Monks, Aaron Novick, Quayshawn Spencer, Michael Weisberg, Daniel Wilkenfeld, 2 anonymous reviewers, and the audience at the 2019 Epistemology of Science Workshop at the Center for Philosophy of Science in Pittsburgh for their help in developing this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Karen Kovaka.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The original online version of this article was revised: the title has been corrected.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kovaka, K. Fighting about frequency. Synthese 199, 7777–7797 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03139-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03139-y

Keywords

Navigation