Skip to main content

Theoretical virtues and theorizing in physics: against the instrumentalist view of simplicity

Abstract

I argue that if (a) simplicity is a theoretical virtue and (b) some theoretical virtues are the constituents of the aims of theorizing in physics—i.e., theory choice and theory development in physics—and (c) scientific rationality is instrumental rationality, then simplicity cannot be a mere means to achieve the aims. I do this by showing that considering simplicity as a mere means brings about counterintuitive ramifications concerning scientific rationality. These counterintuitive ramifications can be avoided if we consider simplicity a constituent of the aims of theorizing in physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes

  1. Different catalogs of theoretical virtues can be found in the works of scientists and philosophers of science at least since Robert Boyle’s “Notes on a Good and an Excellent Hypothesis” (1991, p. 119). Most of these catalogs have considerable overlaps. For some examples, see Hempel (1966, 1983), Quine and Ullian (1978), Kuhn (1977), Newton-Smith (1981), McMullin (1996, 2008), Lacey (1999), Lycan (1985), Douglas (2013), and Keas (2018).

  2. In a response to this paper, Kuhn (1983, p. 565) admits that Hempel’s articulation of the aims of science in terms of theoretical virtues is an “improvement” over his own “puzzle-solving” account of the aim of science. Probably the most detailed account of the aims of science in terms of theoretical virtues can be found in Laudan (1984).

  3. For instance, simplicity is mentioned as a theoretical virtue in all the resources that are cited in footnote 1.

  4. Such approach, though not particularly about theoretical physics, is adopted by Kuhn (1977), McMullin (1982), Laudan (1984), and Longino (1990, Chapter 4).

  5. As Kuhn (1977) argues, this does not mean that different members of the community cannot have legitimate disagreements about the interpretation of theoretical virtues or their relative weight in theory choice.

  6. For a non-instrumental account of scientific rationality, see Friedman (2001, pp. 53–68).

  7. Here, a distinction can be made between “subjective rationality” (or rationality vis-à-vis a scientist’s beliefs) and “objective rationality” (or rationality vis-à-vis available evidence). A scientist’s theory choice, for instance, might be subjectively rational because she believes that the chosen theory best instantiates the aim-TVs, but objectively irrational because her relevant beliefs are false—i.e., inconsistent with the evidence. In this paper, I avoid the problem of possible conflicts between objective vs. subjective rationality by assuming that scientists’ relevant beliefs are always justified, namely, their beliefs are supported with the relevant facts of the matter. So, for instance, if scientists believe that T1 is more accurate (or less explanatory powerful) that T2, they are justified in their belief because their belief accord with the evidence. This, of course, does not mean that their beliefs are always true.

  8. As Rowbottom (2010, pp. 212–13) suggests, the achievability of the aims by following the norms or using the means can be also understood probabilistically: it is rational to adopt some means if it makes it more probable to achieve the aims. As we shall see, my arguments can also address probabilistic instrumentality. For the sake of brevity, in what follows, I primarily talk about “achieving the aims” rather than “making achieving the aims more probable.”.

References

  • Boyle, R. (1991). Selected philosophical papers of Robert Boyle. (M. A. Stewart, Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Descartes, R. (2006). A discourse on the method of correctly conducting one’s reason and seeking truth in the sciences. (I. Maclean, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Douglas, H. (2013). The value of cognitive values. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 796–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2001). Dynamics of reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1989). Scientific rationality as instrumental rationality. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 20(3), 377–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1979a). Scientific rationality: Analytic vs. pragmatic perspectives. In T. S. Geraets (Ed.), Rationality To-Day/La Rationalite Ajiourd’hui (pp. 46–58). Ottawa: The University of Ottawa Press.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1979b/2001). Scientific rationality: Normative versus descriptive construals. In J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), The Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel: Studies in Science, Explanation, and Rationality (pp. 357–71). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1983). Valuation and objectivity in science. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.), Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis (pp. 73–100). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keas, M. N. (2018). Systematizing the theoretical virtues. Synthese, 195(6), 2761–2793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1983). Rationality and theory choice. The Journal of Philosophy, 80(10), 563–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free?: Values and scientific understanding. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1985). Epistemic value. Synthese, 64(2), 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1982). Values in science. In: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1982, pp. 3–28.

  • McMullin, E. (1996). Epistemic virtue and theory appraisal. In I. Douven & L. Horsten (Eds.), Realism in the sciences (pp. 13–34). Leuven, Belgium: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (2008). The virtues of a good theory. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 498–508). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W. H. (1981). The rationality of science. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. P. (2010). Evolutionary epistemology and the aim of science. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88(2), 209–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. P. (2014). Aimless science. Synthese, 191(6), 1211–1221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2015). Ockham’s razors: A user’s manual. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2016). Ockham’s razors: A user’s manual. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/ockhams-razors-a-users-manual/.

  • Thagard, P. (2004). Rationality and science. In A. R. Mele & P. Rawling (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of rationality (pp. 363–379). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Anjan Chakravertty, Janet Kourany, Faeze Fazeli, Oliver Traldi, and two anonymous referees for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mousa Mohammadian.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mohammadian, M. Theoretical virtues and theorizing in physics: against the instrumentalist view of simplicity. Synthese 199, 4819–4828 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-03004-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-03004-4

Keywords

  • Simplicity
  • Theoretical virtues
  • The aims of science
  • Scientific rationality
  • Instrumental rationality