Abstract
Typically, a less fundamental theory, or structure, emerging from a more fundamental one is an example of synchronic emergence. A model (and the physical state it describes) emerging from a prior model (state) upon which it nevertheless depends is an example of diachronic emergence. The case of spacetime emergent from quantum gravity and quantum cosmology challenges these two conceptions of emergence. Here, I propose two more-general conceptions of emergence, analogous to the synchronic and diachronic ones, but which are potentially applicable to the case of emergent spacetime: an inter-level, hierarchical conception, and an intra-level, ‘flat’ conception. I then explore whether, and how, these ideas may be applicable in the case of several putative examples of relativistic spacetime emergent from the non-spatiotemporal structures described by different approaches to quantum gravity, and of spacetime emergent from a non-spatiotemporal ‘big bang’ state according to different examples of quantum cosmology.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.









Notes
Ignoring the problem of dark matter, which may indicate a problem with GR at large length scales.
See, e.g., Burgess (2004).
This characterisation is supposed to be compatible with the idea of ‘top-down causation’, depending on how the ‘higher level’ and ‘lower level’ labels are applied in the particular proposals (e.g., ‘higher level’ could not refer to a less fundamental theory on this account).
See Crowther (2018).
Here, ‘micro’ is used purely in a figurative sense, as a means of distinguishing the degrees of freedom described by QG from those (‘macro’ degrees of freedom) of current physics. ‘High-energy scales’ and ‘short-length scales’ are used interchangeably, and are also used to signify the domain expected to be described by QG. The scare quotes indicate that this may not literally be true, because QG may describe a regime where the idea of length (and, correspondingly, energy) are not meaningful.
See, e.g., the discussion in Wüthrich (2017).
While I will argue that these examples plausibly can be interpreted as candidates for spacetime emergence, however, there is also scope for arguing that we don’t need to understand them as emergence, and instead adopt a different metaphysical interpretation of the relationship between spacetime and the structures described by QG; cf. Le Bihan (2018). Another option is to utilise the idea of ‘partial functionalism’, rather than metaphysical accounts of emergence, cf. Baron (2019).
See Footnote 6.
See also Franklin (2018), who distinguishes two different senses of autonomy related to EFT and theoretical naturalness.
This is a loose characterisation, and one may debate its adequacy in general (particularly regarding the idea of “physical quantities”). Questions regarding the specific nature of dualities are beyond the scope of this paper, but interested readers are encouraged to dig into the philosophical literature, including Butterfield (2018), Dawid (2017), Read and Møller-Nielsen (2018) and the special issue Castellani and Rickles (2017).
Cf. the philosophy references in Footnote 16.
Note that an additional argument for F’s relative fundamentality needs to be provided here.
While the Dependence condition is apparently generally satisfied in the (Approx) schema, via the coarse graining, for example, it is less-obvious that this is the case for approaches that fit (BrokenMap).
Thanks to a referee for emphasising this point.
For more on LQG, see Rovelli (2004), Rovelli and Vidotto (2014). Note that this latter reference is much more up-to-date than the brief sketch of the kinematic aspect of the theory that I present here; in particular, it has much more detail on the dynamics of the theory, using the covariant approach to LQG.
Shech (2019) also suggests weakening the novelty condition along these lines.
In fact, causal set cosmology suggests that the universe underwent many cycles of expansion, stasis, and contraction before our ‘big bang’ event. This is used to explain particular aspects of our current universe that are otherwise striking to cosmologists. See, Sorkin (2000).
We could have an even stronger basis for Novelty if we take the big bang state to be emergent compared to the state that penultimately precedes it, i.e., the causet at Stage \(N - 1\), rather than the causet at Stage N. In this case, the contrast would be between a state that has ontological indeterminism, versus one that has no ontological indeterminism.
Recall that in our positive conception of emergence, novelty is symmetric and relative: a measure of how the emergent and basis states differ from one another. Thus, Novelty does not require that the novel power be possessed by the emergent state.
As suggested by Huggett and Wüthrich in private correspondence.
In other LQC models, however, there may be a notion of continuous evolution with respect to the scalar field as ‘internal time’, and arguably the ‘big bounce’ picture is better-supported.
Cf. Barrau and Grain (2016)
But note that this is not entirely accurate, either, since it implies we can consider the dual of some cellular decomposition (in this case we just have a single cell).
Thank you to a referee for suggesting this point.
Although this may be a misleading representation: the points of the time dimension at other times of course refer to spatial slices in the whole of spacetime, and this one ‘point’ refers just to a space with one more dimension. Thanks to Nick Huggett for this clarification.
References
Bain, J. (2008). Condensed matter physics and the nature of spacetime. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime II (pp. 301–329). Oxford: Elsevier. (Chapter 16).
Bain, J. (2013). Effective field theories. In B. Batterman (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of physics (pp. 224–254). New York: Oxford University Press.
Barceló, C., Liberati, S., & Visser, M. (2011). Analogue gravity. Living Reviews in Relativity. http://www.livingreviews.org/lrr-2011-3.
Baron, S. (2019). The curious case of spacetime emergence. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01306-z.
Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2014). Causation in a timeless world. Synthese, 191(12), 2867–2886.
Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2015). Causation sans time. American Philosophical Quarterly, 52, 27–40.
Barrau, A., & Grain, J. (2016). Cosmology without time: What to do with a possible signature change from quantum gravitational origin? arXiv:1607.07589v1.
Batterman, R. W. (2005). Critical phenomena and breaking drops: Infinite idealizations in physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36(2), 225–244.
Batterman, R. W. (2011). Emergence, singularities, and symmetry breaking. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1031–1050.
Bojowald, M. (2011). Quantum cosmology: A fundamental description of the universe. New York: Springer.
Brahma, S. (2017). Emergence of time in loop quantum gravity. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/13158/.
Burgess, C. P. (2004). Quantum gravity in everyday life: General relativity as an effective field theory. Living Reviews in Relativity. www.livingreviews.org/lrr-2004-5.
Butterfield, J. (2011a). Emergence, reduction and supervenience: A varied landscape. Foundations of Physics, 41(6), 920–959.
Butterfield, J. (2011b). Less is different: Emergence and reduction reconciled. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1065–1135.
Butterfield, J. (2018). On dualities and equivalences between physical theories. arXiv:1806.01505.
Butterfield, J., & Isham, C. (1999). On the emergence of time in quantum gravity. In J. Butterfield (Ed.), The arguments of time (pp. 116–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Castellani, E., & Rickles, D. (2017). Introduction to special issue on dualities. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59, 1–5.
Crowther, K. (2015). Decoupling emergence and reduction in physics. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5(3), 419–445.
Crowther, K. (2016). Effective spacetime: Understanding emergence in effective field theory and quantum gravity. Heidelberg: Springer.
Crowther, K. (2018). Inter-theory relations in quantum gravity: Correspondence, reduction, and emergence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 63, 74–85.
Dawid, R. (2017). String dualities and empirical equivalence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59, 21–29.
de Haro, S. (2017). Dualities and emergent gravity: Gauge/gravity duality. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59, 109–125.
Dieks, D., van Dongen, J., & de Haro, S. (2015). Emergence in holographic scenarios for gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, 203–216.
Dowker, F. (2005). Causal sets and the deep structure of spacetime. In A. Ashtekar (Ed.), 100 years of relativity: Space-time structure (pp. 445–467). Singapore: World Scientific.
Franklin, A. (2018). Whence the effectiveness of effective field theories? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy050.
Freidel, L. (2005). Group field theory: An overview. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 44(10), 1769–1783.
Guay, A., & Sartenaer, O. (2016). A new look at emergence. Or when after is different. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 6(2), 297–322.
Hartmann, S. (2001). Effective field theories, reductionism and scientific explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32(2), 267–301.
Hawking, S., King, A., & McCarthy, P. (1976). A new topology for curved space-time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 17(2), 174–181.
Henson, J. (2009). The causal set approach to quantum gravity. In D. Oriti (Ed.), Approaches to quantum gravity: Toward a new understanding of space, time and matter (pp. 393–413). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2013). Emergent spacetime and empirical (in)coherence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(3), 276–285.
Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2018). The (a)temporal emergence of spacetime. Philosophy of Science, 85(5), 1190–1203.
Konopka, T., Markopoulou, F., & Severini, S. (2008). Quantum graphity: A model of emergent locality. Physical Review D, 77(10), 104029.
Le Bihan, B. (2018). Space emergence in contemporary physics: Why we do not need fundamentality, layers of reality and emergence. Disputatio, 10(49), 71–95.
Levichev, V. (1987). Prescribing the conformal geometry of a Lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure. Soviet Mathematics Doklady, 35, 452–455.
Linnemann, N. S., & Visser, M. R. (2018). Hints towards the emergent nature of gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 64, 1–13.
Malament, D. (1977). The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 18(7), 1399–1404.
Markopoulou, F. (2009). New directions in background independent quantum gravity. In D. Oriti (Ed.), Approaches to quantum gravity (pp. 129–149). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morrison, M. (2012). Emergent physics and micro-ontology. Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 141–166.
Oriti, D. (Ed.). (2009). The group field theory approach to quantum gravity. In Approaches to quantum gravity: Toward a new understanding of space time and matter (pp. 310–331). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Oriti, D. (2014). Disappearance and emergence of space and time in quantum gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 46, 186–199.
Oriti, D. (2018a). The Bronstein hypercube of quantum gravity. arXiv:1803.02577.
Oriti, D. (2018b). Levels of spacetime emergence in quantum gravity. arXiv:1807.04875.
Penrose, R. (1999). The central programme of twistor theory. Chaos, Solitons and Fractals, 10(2–3), 581–611.
Penrose, R. (2002). Gravitational collapse: The role of general relativity. General Relativity and Gravitation, 34(7), 1141–1165.
Read, J., & Møller-Nielsen, T. (2018). Motivating dualities. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1817-5.
Rickles, D. (2013). AdS/CFT duality and the emergence of spacetime. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(3), 312–320.
Rideout, D., & Sorkin, R. (1999). Classical sequential growth model for causal sets. Journal of Physics Conference Series, 174, 024002.
Rovelli, C. (2004). Quantum gravity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rovelli, C., & Vidotto, F. (2014). Covariant loop quantum gravity: An elementary introduction to quantum gravity and spinfoam theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sartenaer, O. (2018). Flat emergence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(S1), 225–250.
Shech, E. (2019). Philosophical issues concerning phase transitions and anyons: Emergence, reduction, and explanatory fictions. Erkenntnis, 84(3), 585–615.
Sorkin, R. (2009). Does locality fail at intermediate length scales? In D. Oriti (Ed.), Approaches to quantum ravity: Toward a new understanding of space, time and matter (pp. 26–43). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sorkin, R. D. (2000). Indications of causal set cosmology. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 39(7), 1731–1736.
Sorkin, R. D. (2005). Causal sets: Discrete gravity (notes for the valdivia summer school). In D. M. A. Gomberoff (Ed.), Lectures on quantum gravity, proceedings of the Valdivia summer school, Valdivia, Chile, January 2002. Plenum. arXiv:gr-qc/0309009.
Surya, S. (2019). The causal set approach to quantum gravity. Living Reviews in Relativity. arXiv:1903.11544.
’t Hooft, G. (1993). Dimensional reduction in quantum gravity. arXiv:gr-qc/9310026.
Tallant, J. (2019). Causation in a timeless world? Inquiry, 62(3), 300–316.
Teh, N. (2013). Holography and emergence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(3), 300–311.
Verlinde, E. (2011). On the origin of gravity and the laws of Newton. Journal of High Energy Physics, 1104, 029.
Vistarini, T. (2017). Holographic space and time: Emergent in what sense? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59, 126–135. Dualities in Physics.
Wüthrich, C. (2012). The structure of causal sets. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43(2), 223–241.
Wüthrich, C. (2017). Raiders of the lost spacetime. In D. Lehmkuhl (Ed.), Towards a theory of spacetime theories (pp. 297–335). London: Birkhäuser.
Wüthrich, C. (2019). The emergence of space and time. In S. Gibb, R. F. Hendry, & T. Lancaster (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Emergence (pp. 315–326). London: Routledge.
Wüthrich, C., & Callender, C. (2017). What becomes of a causal set? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(3), 907–925.
Acknowledgements
Thanks to the participants at the conference on Diachronic Emergence in Cologne, and especially to Olivier Sartenaer and Andreas Hüttemann for organising it. Thanks to Christian Wüthrich, Nick Huggett, Augustin Baas, Sam Baron, as well as audiences in Perth, Turin, Oxford, Lausanne, and Boston. Finally, thanks to the referees for the journal for their helpful feedback. Funding was provided by Schweizerischer Nationalfonds zur Förderung der Wissenschaftlichen Forschung (Grant No. 105212 165702).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Crowther, K. As below, so before: ‘synchronic’ and ‘diachronic’ conceptions of spacetime emergence. Synthese 198, 7279–7307 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02521-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02521-1
Keywords
- Emergence
- Quantum gravity
- Cosmology
- Spacetime
- Space
- Time
- Flat emergence
- Hierarchical emergence
- Levels
- Fundamentality
- Diachronic emergence
- Synchronic emergence
- Holography
- Duality
- Geometrogenesis