Abstract
In this article I defend pluralist theory against various objections. First, I argue that although traditional theories may also account for multiple ways to achieve social understanding, they still put some emphasis on one particular epistemic strategy (e.g., theory or simulation). Pluralist theory, in contrast, rejects the so-called ‘default assumption’ that there is any primary or default method in social understanding. Second, I illustrate that pluralist theory needs to be distinguished from integration theory. On one hand, integration theory faces the difficulty of trying to combine traditional theories of social understanding that have contradictory background assumptions. On the other hand, pluralist theory goes beyond integrating traditional theories by accounting for a variety of factors that may play a role in social understanding but have been (widely) neglected in such theories, including stereotype activation, social and personal relationships, contextual features, individual moods, perceptions, and so on. Third, I argue that if the default assumption is rejected, pluralist theorists need to provide another positive account of why particular cognitive processes are more likely to come into play in a specific instance of social understanding than others in order to provide a genuine alternative to traditional theories. I discuss three versions of pluralist theory that meet this challenge by pointing to normativity, fluency, and interaction.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Change history
07 March 2020
A Correction to this paper has been published: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02552-z
Notes
Since pluralist theory is not devoted to any particular view of cognition per se, it is perfectly possible that philosophers who endorse different but not contradictory views of cognition team up to explore the varieties of social understanding from a pluralist viewpoint. For example, Fiebich et al. (2017) agree with respect to pluralism in social cognition but differ in their views of whether cognition is enactive (Hutto and Myin 2017; Gallagher 2017a) or whether to remain neutral with respect to endorsing neither enactivism nor cognitivism, though sympathizing with dynamic embodied views of cognition (e.g., de Bruin and Kaestner 2012) when it comes to social understanding in interactive settings (Fiebich 2015, chapt. 4).
Note that the distinction between Type 1 and Type 2 processes resembles the 2-System approach defended by Fiebich and Coltheart (2015), but it is neither essential for integration theory nor pluralist theory to advocate a 2-System view of cognition.
Anika Fiebich (2015) developed a pluralist approach to social understanding in framework of her doctoral thesis independently from Kristin Andrew’s work and inspired by scientific discussions with Maxoltheart (Fiebich and Coltheart 2015). Unfortunately, she only heard about Andrew’s approach when the book ‘How apes read minds’ appeared in 2012 shortly before submitting her thesis at the Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany, so that a substantial discussion of Andrew’s approach in the thesis (published three years later in roughly its original version according to German law) was not possible anymore.
References
Andrews, K. (2008). It’s in your nature. A pluralistic folk psychology. Synthese, 165(1), 13–29.
Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Andrews, K. (2015a). The folk psychological spiral: Explanation, regulation, and language. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(Spindel Supplement), 50–67.
Andrews, K. (2015b). Pluralistic folk psychology and varieties of self-knowledge: An exploration. Philosophical Explorations, 18(2), 280–294.
Andrews, K. (2017). Pluralistic folk psychology in humans and other apes. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The routledge handbook o the social mind (pp. 117–138). London: Routledge.
Apperly, I. (2008). Beyond simulation-theory and theory–theory: Why social neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”. Cognition, 107, 266–283.
Barlassina, L., & Gordon, R. M. (2017). Folk psychology as mental simulation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bohl, V. (2015a). We read minds to shape relationships. Philosophical Psychology, 28(5), 674–694.
Bohl, V. (2015b). Continuing debates on direct social perception: Some notes on Gallagher’s analysis of “the new hybrids”. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 466–471.
Bohl, V., & van den Bos, W. (2012). Toward an integrative account of social cognition: Marrying theory of mind and interactionism to study the interplay of type 1 and type 2 processes. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6, 274. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00274
Borg, E. (2007). If mirror neurons are the answer, what was the question? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14, 5–19.
Buckner, C. (2014). The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mind-reading. Mind and Language, 29(5), 566–589.
Butterfill, S. (2012). Interacting mindreaders. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 841–863.
Carpendale, J. I. M., & Lewis, C. (2004). Constructing an understanding of mind: The development of children’s social understanding within social interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 79–151.
Carruthers, P. (1996). Simulation and self-knowledg: A defence of theory–theory. In P. Carruthers & P. K. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind (pp. 22–28). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2016). Two systems for mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 7, 141–162.
Cogsdill, E. J., Todorov, A., Spelke, E. S., & Banaji, M. R. (2014). Inferring character from faces: A developmental study. Psychological Science, 25(5), 1132–1139.
de Bruin, L., & Kaestner, L. (2012). Dynamic embodied cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 541–563.
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Does social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(10), 441–447.
Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1–18.
Fabricius, W. V., Boyer, T., Weimer, A. A., & Carroll, K. (2010). True or false: Do five-year-olds understand belief? Developmental Psychology, 46, 1402–1416.
Fiebich, A. (2014). Mindreading with ease? Fluence and belief-reasoning in 4- to 5-year-olds. Synthese, 191(5), 929–9244.
Fiebich, A. (2015). Varieties of social understanding. Paderborn: Mentis Verlag GmbH.
Fiebich, A. (2017). Pluralism, social cognition, and interaction in autism. Philosophical Psychology, 30(1–2), 161–184.
Fiebich, A., & Coltheart, M. (2015). Various ways to understand other minds: Towards a pluralistic approach to the explanation of social understanding. Mind and Language, 30(3), 235–258.
Fiebich, A., Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2017). Pluralism, interaction, and the ontogeny of social cognition. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The routledge handbook o the social mind (pp. 208–221). London: Routledge.
Froese, T., & di Paolo, E. (2011). The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics & Cognition, 19(1), 1–36.
Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 83–107.
Gallagher, S. (2008). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 535–543.
Gallagher, S. (2015). The new hybrids: Continuing debates on social perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 452–465.
Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. (2017b). The significance and meaning of others. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, enaction, and culture (pp. 217–227). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallagher, S., & Fiebich, A. (2019). Being pluralist about understanding others: Contexts and communicative practices. In A. Avramides & M. Parrott (Eds.), Knowing and understanding other minds (pp. 63–78). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Gallese, V., & Sinigaglia, C. (2011). What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends in Cognitive Science, 15(11), 512–519.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2005). Folk psychology as a model. Philosophers’ Imprint, 5, 1–16.
Goldman, A. (2002). Simulation theory and mental concepts. In J. Dokic & J. Proust (Eds.), Simulation and knowledge of action (pp. 1–19). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mind-reading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goldman, A. I. (2012). Theory of mind. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science (pp. 402–424). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gopnik, A. (1998). The scientist as child. In A. Gopnik & A. Meltzoff (Eds.), Words, thoughts, and theories (pp. 13–47). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning mechanisms and the theory theory. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1085–1108.
Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1(2), 158–171.
Gray, C. (2000). Writing social stories with Carol Grey. Arlington, TX: Future Horizons.
Heal, J. (2003). Mind, reason and imagination: Selected essays in philosophy of mind and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heal, J. (2013). Social anti-individualism, co-cognitivism, and second person authority. Mind, 122, 339–371.
Herschbach, M. (2008). Folk psychological and phenomenological accounts of social perception. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 223–235.
Hirsch, E. D. (1965). Truth and method in interpretation. Review of Metaphysics, 18(3), 488–507.
Hurley, S. (2008). Understanding simulation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(3), 755–774.
Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books MIT Press.
Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism. Basic minds meet content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. London: Penguin Books.
Krueger, J. (2012). Seeing mind in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 149–173.
Lavelle, J. S. (2012). Theory–theory and the direct perception of mental states. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(2), 213–230.
Leslie, A. M. (1987). Children’s understanding of the mental world. In R. L. Gregory (Ed.), The Oxford companion to the mind (pp. 139–142). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leslie, A. M., Friedman, O., & German, T. P. (2004). Core mechanisms in ‘theory of mind’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(12), 528–533.
Macrae, C. N., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Milne, A. B. (1995). The dissection of selection in person perception: Inhibitory processes in social stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 397–407.
Maibom, H. L. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind and Language, 20, 237–257.
Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto & M. M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 137–156). New York: Springer.
Michael, H., Christensen, W., & Overgaard, S. (2014). Mindreading as social expertise. Synthese, 191, 817–840.
Moore, R. (2016). Meaning and ostension in great ape gestural communication. Animal Cognition, 19(1), 223–231.
Newen, A. (2015a). Understanding others—The person model theory. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind: 26(T) (pp. 1–28). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570320.
Newen, A. (2015b). A multiplicity view for social cognition: Defending a coherent framework—A reply to Lisa Quadt. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind: 26(R) (pp. 1–7). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958571167.
Newen, A., & Schlicht, T. (2009). Understanding other minds. A criticism of Goldman’s simulation theory and an outline of the person model theory. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 79(1), 209–242.
Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford Cognitive Science Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Oppenheimer, D. M. (2008). The secret life of fluency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(6), 237–241.
Overgaard, S. (2017). The unobservability thesis. Synthese, 194, 743–760.
Quadt, L. (2015). Multiplicity needs coherence—Towards a unifying framework for social understanding—a commentary on Albert Newen. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind 26(C) (pp. 1–18). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958571112.
Spaulding, S. (2018a). Mindreading beyond belief: A more comprehensive conception of how we understand others. Philosophy Compass, 13(11), e12526.
Spaulding, S. (2018b). Do you see what I see? How social differences influence mindreading, Synthese, 195(9), 4009–4030.
Stapelton, M., & Ward, D. (2012). Es are good. Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended. In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction: the role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness (pp. 89–104). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
Trevarthen, C. B. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before speech (pp. 321–348). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Westra, E. (2018). Character and theory of mind: An integrative approach. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1217–1241.
Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Acknowledgements
Funding was provided by Università degli Studi di Milano.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Fiebich, A. In defense of pluralist theory. Synthese 198, 6815–6834 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02490-5
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02490-5