Skip to main content
Log in

Confabulation does not undermine introspection for propositional attitudes

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to some, such as Carruthers (Behav Brain Sci 32:121–138, 2009; Philos Phenomenol Res 80:76–111, 2010; The opacity of mind: an integrative theory of self-knowledge, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011; The centered mind: what the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2015), the confabulation data (experimental data showing subjects making false psychological self-ascriptions) undermine the view that we can know our propositional attitudes by introspection. He believes that these data favour his interpretive sensory-access (ISA) theory—the view that self-knowledge of our propositional attitudes always involves self-interpretation of our sensations, behaviour, or situational cues. This paper will review some of the confabulation data and conclude that the presence and pattern of these data do not substantiate the claim that we cannot introspect our propositional attitudes. As a consequence of this discussion, I conclude that the ISA theory is not well supported by the empirical data.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This set of mental states is also sometimes referred to as ‘intentional mental states’. See Searle (1983, p. 3) for a more comprehensive list of these states.

  2. Theorists such as Lycan maintain that one’s mechanism of inner sense works like one’s mechanism of outer sense (visual perception), except that inner sense’s objects of detection include beliefs, desires, intentions, and so on. According to another of the view’s proponents, Paul Churchland, this makes the view ‘no more (and no less) mysterious’ ([1988] 2013, p. 122) than outer sense. It may be objected here, however, that inner sense (e.g., the detection of a belief) is far more mysterious than outer sense (e.g., the seeing of a red rose). This is because it seems quite mysteriousness as to how one could know whether one had a belief that P, rather than say a wish or desire that P, by simply looking inward. What would one look for in one’s internal search? It is such a mystery that opens the door to scepticism about introspection, and thus makes sceptical accounts of self-knowledge important to address. See Byrne (2018, chapter 2) for a recent discussion of the main objections to the inner sense view.

  3. In previous work, see Andreotta (2017), I have argued that the transparency method is the most promising of these theories. In what follows, however, I make no explicit reference to this view. I am only interested in addressing scepticism about our ability to know our own propositional attitudes in a way that is different from the way that other people gain knowledge of them. Only once this scepticism has been addressed can we begin to assess views which seek to account for this difference.

  4. It is worth pointing out that not all philosophers have chosen to use the word ‘introspection’ this broadly. Gertler (2011), for instance, uses the word ‘introspection’ only for processes which involve inner perception. According to Gertler, even if a view states that there is a unique way in which one can acquire knowledge of one’s own mind, that view should not be called ‘introspective’ unless it also involves inner perception. See Andreotta (2017), chapter one, for a theory-neutral definition of introspection.

  5. Smithies and Stoljar (2012) note that there are multiple ways in which the difference thesis may be construed. They note that introspection may differ from other ways of gaining knowledge—such as by perception or testimony—in epistemological respects and psychological respects (as well as many other ways).

  6. Carruthers (2011, p. xii) says that his own view is closest to Gazzaniga’s (1998). He situates the ISA theory between Gopnik’s (1993) view—which he claims goes too far; and Wegner’s (2002) and Wilson’s (2002) views—which he claims do not go far enough. One reason to focus on Carruthers’ view here, as opposed to the view outlined in Gopnik’s earlier work, is that Carruthers’s view draws upon recent empirical data. As Rey (2013, p. 262), points out, a major piece of evidence for Gopnik’s (1993) view—evidence from the false belief studies—is now seen as highly controversial (see Onishi and Baillargeon 2005).

  7. In this paper, I will employ the term ‘confabulation’ in accordance with how Carruthers (2011) understands it—namely, to refer to any false psychological self-ascription. It should be noted that there are controversies about the definition and applicably of the term that will not be considered here. See Hirstein (2009) for a discussion of such controversies.

  8. Carruthers expands upon the ISA theory in chapter 2 of his recent book The Centred Mind (2015).

  9. It may be objected that this view is easily refuted because one will still be able to self-attribute one’s own propositional attitudes even if one is in a dark room, unable to observe any of one’s own behaviour (see Rey 2013). Carruthers’ (2011, p. 158) own response to this objection is that such a person will still have visual imagery, inner speech, and affective feelings to draw upon.

  10. Carruthers leaves open the question of what constitutes a perceptually-embedded attitude (2011, p. 83). For example, he points out that a grandmaster in chess may be able to ‘see literally…that White is doomed to lose’ (2011, p. 84) after looking at a particular chess configuration.

  11. Carruthers’ contention that we have special (or introspective) access to our sensory based propositional attitudes because such attitudes are bound to the sensations they are about is by no means obvious, however. The binding position could be false and we could still have special (or introspective) access to our sensory based proposition attitudes. Such a position would not sit easily with ISA theory, though I do not consider the point any further here.

  12. I suspect that we would not see the same results with stronger beliefs people held. For example, if people were asked about what they believed about the place they were born, or what they believe their brother’s name to be.

  13. This was noted in an experiment performed by Fredrickson et al. (1998). See chapter 3 of Bargh’s (2017) recent book Before You Know It for many similar experiments involving priming.

  14. While it is true that the ISA theory does not predict that subjects will always make erroneous self-attributions, the cases involving errors are important, as they are the cases that are supposed to reveal how we normally do attribute our propositional attitudes.

  15. Another significant challenge to Carruthers’ preferred interpretation of this data—quite apart from the concerns raised here—comes from the findings from a direct replication of these experiments carried out by Johnson et al. (2014). Using a much larger sample size than the one used by Schnall et al. (2008), Johnson et al. (2014) found that similar results did not materialise—that is, the experimenters failed to find the same kind of connection between one’s sensations and one’s moral judgements that was present in the original experiments. This failure to replicate the original results means that the conclusion that subjects are confabulating because of misleading perceptual cues would not seem to be the best explanation of the patterning of the data.

  16. Following Cassam (2010), I understand judgements to be conscious mental actions, which are related to beliefs, which are typically more stable, longstanding, mental states. Unlike Cassam, however, I think the two typically go together with a greater congruity. I agree with Nico Silins, who says that if you ‘judge that p, you have justification to believe that you believe that p’ (see 2012, p. 302). I raise this distinction because in the examples discussed here, Carruthers claims that a judgement has been confabulated. Given the close connection between judgement and belief, I think that these cases could have just as easily be classified as cases involving belief.

  17. Not everyone agrees that the confabulation interpretation is correct here. For example: Goldman (2006, p. 232), considers the possibility that the left and right hemispheres may be separate streams of consciousness, and so the subject’s self-attribution is not, strictly speaking, an example of confabulation because the psychological ascription refers to a different stream of consciousness. Goldman does not press this response, however. Fiala and Nichols (2009), moreover, suggest that there are some examples in the split-brain literature where subjects express low confidence in their self-reports. If this is true, it may not be right to identify such a case as one of confabulation, because the subject would not be confident in his avowal. And Rey (2013, p. 265 ft. 9) points out that there has not been a sustained attempt to determine whether the split-brain subjects express any hesitancy when they give their answers. There is also the possibility that even without displays of hesitancy, the subjects may nonetheless possess an ability to introspect that is difficult to detect in usual performance.

  18. This quote was brought to my attention in Balsvik (2017).

  19. According to a Google Scholar search, in September 2018, the paper has had over 12,000 citations.

  20. Although the two are closely related, it is important to distinguish introspection from privileged access (the thesis that our own self-ascriptions are epistemically privileged). This is because, as Byrne (2018, p. 9) points out, the two can come apart. One could argue that we do not have introspective access to our propositional attitudes, and yet still claim that we have privileged access to them (perhaps because we are around ourselves more often). In this paper, I am only concerned with the question ‘Can humans introspect their own propositional attitudes?’

  21. See Schmidt et al. (2017).

  22. See Keeling (2018), for a discussion of the question ‘Why do we confabulate?’ For a discussion about some of the potential epistemic benefits of confabulation see Bortolotti (2018).

References

  • Andreotta, A. (2017). First-person authority and its limits. PhD thesis, The University of Western Australia.

  • Balsvik, E. (2017). Interpretivism, first-person authority, and confabulation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 47, 311–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. (2017). Before you know it: The unconscious reasons we do what we do. London: Windmill Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking my mind: Expression and self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2018). Stranger than fiction: Costs and benefits of everyday confabulation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 9, 227–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. ([1987] 1999). Intention, plans, and practical reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

  • Briñol, P., & Petty, R. E. (2003). Overt head movements and persuasion: A self-validation analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 1123–1139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2018). Transparency and self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2010). Introspection: Divided and partly eliminated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 76–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2015). The centered mind: What the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2010). Judging, believing and thinking. Philosophical Issues, 20, 80–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2014). Self-knowledge for humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. ([1988] 2013). Matter and consciousness (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Dretske, F. (2003). How do you know you are not a zombie? In B. Gertler (Ed.), Privileged access: Philosophical accounts of self-knowledge. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, J. (2013). Transparent minds: A study of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiala, B., & Nichols, S. (2009). Confabulation, confidence, and introspection (commentary on Peter Carruthers). Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 144–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, D. H. (2003). Expression and the inner. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L., Roberts, T. A., Noll, S. M., Quinn, D. M., & Twenge, J. M. (1998). That swimsuit becomes you: Sex differences in self-objectification, restrained eating, and math performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 269–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (1995). Consciousness and the cerebral hemispheres. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (1998). The mind’s past. Berkley: California University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (2000). Cerebral specialization and inter-hemispheric communication: Does the corpus callosum enable the human condition? Brain, 123, 1293–1326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (2011). Who’s in charge? Free will and the science of the brain. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. (2011). Self-knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. (2012). Renewed acquaintance. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (1993). How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16, 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, L., Johansson, P., Tärning, B., Sikström, S., & Deutgen, T. (2010). Magic at the marketplace: Choice blindness for the taste of jam and the smell of tea. Cognition, 117, 54–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, L., Strandberg, T., Pärnamets, P., Lind, A., Tärning, B., & Johansson, P. (2013). How the polls can be both spot on and dead wrong: Using choice blindness to shift political attitudes and voter intentions. PLoS ONE, 8, e60554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirstein, W. (2009). Introduction: What is confabulation? In W. Hirstein (Ed.), Confabulation: Views from neuroscience, psychiatry, psychology and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurlburt, R. T., & Schwitzgebel, E. (2007). Describing inner experience? Proponent meets skeptic. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, P., Hall, L., Sikström, S., & Olsson, A. (2005). Failure to detect mismatches between intention and outcome in a simple decision task. Science, 310, 116–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. J., Cheung, F., & Donnellan, M. B. (2014). Does cleanliness influence moral judgments? A direct replication of Schnall, Benton, and Harvey (2008). Social Psychology, 45, 209–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeling, S. (2018). Confabulation and rational obligations for self-knowledge. Philosophical Psychology, 31, 1215–1238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know. Psychological Review, 84, 231–295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old Infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308, 255–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (2008). (Even higher-order) intentionality without consciousness. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 62, 51–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (2013). We are not all “self-blind”: A defense of a modest introspectionism. Mind and Language, 28, 259–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieznik, A., Moscovich, L., Frieiro, A., Figini, J., Catalano, R., Garrido, J. M., et al. (2017). A massive experiment on choice blindness in political decisions: Confidence, confabulation, and unconscious detection of self-deception. PLoS ONE, 12, e0171108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2018). How history gets things wrong: The neuroscience of our addiction to stories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaife, R. (2014). A problem for self-knowledge: The implications of taking confabulation seriously. Acta Analytica, 29, 469–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, L., Skvortsova, V., Kullen, C., Weber, B., & Plassmann, H. (2017). How context alters value: The brain’s valuation and affective regulation system link price cues to experienced taste pleasantness. Scientific Reports, 7, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 1096–1109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531–553.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012). Introspection, what? In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silins, N. (2012). Judgment as a guide to belief. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, D. J., & Rensink, R. A. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present, and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 16–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D., & Stoljar, D. (2012). Introspection and consciousness: An overview. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wareham, J., Blackwell, B. S., Bonnie, B., & Boots, D. P. (2018). Complainant’s physical attractiveness and juristic judgments of blame and punishment in physical, domestic, and sexual assault scenarios. Deviant Behavior, 40, 219–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Miri Albahari, Nin Kirkham, Daniel Stoljar, Alex Byrne, André Gallois, Sean Ramsey, and Harriet Levenston for feedback and advice on earlier versions of the paper. I also would like to thank three anonymous referees of this journal for their insightful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam J. Andreotta.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andreotta, A.J. Confabulation does not undermine introspection for propositional attitudes. Synthese 198, 4851–4872 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02373-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02373-9

Keywords

Navigation