Abstract
The concept of “life” certainly is of some use to distinguish birds and beavers from water and stones. This pragmatic usefulness has led to its construal as a categorical predicate that can sift out living entities from non-living ones depending on their possessing specific properties—reproduction, metabolism, evolvability etc. In this paper, we argue against this binary construal of life. Using text-mining methods across over 30,000 scientific articles, we defend instead a degrees-of-life view and show how these methods can contribute to experimental philosophy of science and concept explication. We apply topic-modeling algorithms to identify which specific properties are attributed to a target set of entities (bacteria, archaea, viruses, prions, plasmids, phages and the molecule of adenine). Eight major clusters of properties were identified together with their relative relevance for each target entity (two that relate to metabolism and catalysis, one to genetics, one to evolvability, one to structure, and—rather unexpectedly—three that concern interactions with the environment broadly construed). While aligning with intuitions—for instance about viruses being less alive than bacteria—these quantitative results also reveal differential degrees of performance that have so far remained elusive or overlooked. Taken together, these analyses provide a conceptual “lifeness space” that makes it possible to move away from a categorical construal of life by empirically assessing the relative lifeness of more-or-less alive entities.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.


Notes
This paper builds on the conceptual idea of “lifeness signatures” as proposed by Malaterre (2010b). One aspect of our contribution is to show that such conceptual construal of life can be operationalized and rendered measurable. As noted by one referee for Synthese, our views bear some resemblance with Godfrey-Smith’s Darwinian space (2009) in that both are multidimensional. The two projects pursue however different objectives: a characterization of more-or-less paradigmatically Darwinian populations for Godfrey-Smith, a characterization of more-or-less alive entities in our case. The methods are also different, relatively qualitative in the case of Godfrey-Smith, more quantitative and data-driven in our case. Both instances show the value of thinking multi-dimensionally for conceptual explication.
The analysis of how defining impacts (DL) is beyond the scope of this paper, but see Malaterre (2010c).
The question whether natural kinds should partition the entities of the universe into unambiguous and non-intersecting sets is the object of debate; see e.g. Boyd (1999), Ellis (2001). For the sake of the present discussion, suffice it to say that at least some authors argue simultaneously for a positive answer to (DL-O) and a binary partitioning.
For guidance, one may look at the 100 + definitions listed in Pályi et al. (2002), Popa (2004), most of which take the form of biconditionals delineating life in a binary fashion and without further justification of that binary view. Some authors, though, appeal to phase-transitions or emergent properties that would sharply distinguish life from non-life, e.g. Lange (1996), Luisi (2006); for a critical assessment of these, see Malaterre (2010a).
Along the same line of thoughts, see also the operational role of definitions of life in the search for life elsewhere than on Earth— be it on Mars, on the Jovian moons or, much further away, on exoplanets circling other suns in our galaxy—with the mediation of “biosignatures” (Raulin 2010; Seager et al. 2016), as well as in the search for life in the test-tube to assess whether experimental attempts at creating life have been successful or not (Blain and Szostak 2014).
As pointed to us by a referee, were the categories “alive” and “not-alive” be considered as determinate membership categories (i.e., once something has been found to be a member, that thing is a full member), entities of the gray-zone of lifeness could be considered as borderline cases with indeterminate membership (neither members nor non-members of the two categories “alive” and “not-alive”). As a result, they could be considered as delineating a third determinate membership category. Alternatively, they could be taken as evidence that the categories “alive” and “not-alive” are not determinate membership categories but categories with degrees of membership. Independently of which interpretation one chooses, our point is to stress out that construing the two categories “alive” and “not-alive” as being mutually exclusive and collectively exhaustive categories with determinate membership does not do justice to the variety of entities that populate the world. Hence our argument against (Bi).
This synchronic view can contribute, for instance, to arguments about the lack of clear-cut delineation of biodiversity’s scope when considering ever smaller biological entities (Malaterre 2013).
As an illustration of this point, see the debate on the role of viruses in the origin of DNA in (Forterre 2006).
In Bedau’s framework, the position on the scale of lifeness is a function of the number of interactions. As a consequence, a value of 1 interaction can be achieved either by having 1 functionality and 1 retroactive interaction from this functionality onto itself, or by having 2 functionalities linked by a 1 interaction. With the same reasoning, one can figure out that step 2 entities necessarily have 2 or 3 functionalities, and that step 5 entities necessarily have all three functionalities. From step 5 to step 9, all entities necessarily have all 3 functionalities and are only distinguished by their number of interactions. Functionalities therefore play a secondary role compared to that of interactions.
A referee pointed to us the importance of interactions between functions. Interactions do indeed capture a very relevant feature of living organisms. This is a point emphasized notably by Gántí (2003), and that is central in Bedau’s framework and in other perspectives that are largely focused on designing or engineering protocells. Yet, we argue that characterizing the lifeness of entities concerns, above all, identifying what these entities do (this is a project that is different from the one pursued by Bedau, and complementary). Consider a simple analogy: a sidecar motorbike can be depicted as possessing the functions of ‘motorized propulsion’, of ‘providing seating for a driver’ and of ‘providing seating for a passenger’. This third function clearly is what differentiates a sidecar motorbike from a regular motorbike. The fact that there is an interaction between the sidecar itself and the motorbike to which it is attached is of course crucial but it does not spontaneously arise in the top list of differentiating properties of such sidecar motorbikes compared to regular motorbikes. In biology, the characterization of microorganisms through the identification of genes belonging to different clusters of orthologous groups clearly also illustrates the importance of this perspective (Galperin et al. 2015). Indeed, the significant differentiating factors between microorganisms are taken to be genes that correspond to specific functions, not genes that correspond to interactions between functions.
Note however that not all entities that are classified within the domain Bacteria would appear as uncontroversially alive: as mentioned earlier, the status of the endosymbiont Carsonella ruddii and others clearly is disputed.
This provides an additional element of answer to (FG0), namely that the functional dimensions of common bacteria are the ones to be considered as functional dimensions of lifeness.
One anonymous referee pointed to us the risk that we might be introducing a form of circularity by adopting bacteria as reference for the 1-value of lifeness (somehow similar to the circularity of Bruylants and colleagues). The difference between the two approaches is that, in our case, we take common bacteria such as E. coli as reference point, and then assess the lifeness of any other entity by comparison to this reference point, whereas Bruylants et al. consider that any entity of the tree of life automatically deserves to be at the 1-value of lifeness (relegating the question whether entities ought to be part of the tree of life to scientists’ classificatory practices).
Ideally, we would have liked to conduct our analyses at the granularity of species—so as to clearly identify, in particular, the performance of E. coli and use it as reference point for comparing other species (such as C. ruddii and others). In practice, this was unfortunately not possible: first, it is quite difficult to identify which particular species generic words such as ‘bacteria’ or ‘virus’ refer to; second, species names are rare throughout the corpus, and therefore cannot be reliably used for text-mining purposes (this is a limitation of the methodology we discuss in Sect. 7). We thereby decided to conduct our analyses at a coarser-grained level (hence the choice of target entities such as ‘bacteria’, ‘virus’ etc.). This implies that the lifeness of particular species could not be assessed. It also implies that the actual reference point for the 1-value of lifeness is actually the averaged performance of all bacterial species present in the corpus (and not exclusively of E. coli). This is an area where further research could be conducted, on larger corpuses and with more sophisticated text-mining tools.
As pointed to us by one referee, there are other reasons why properties could be strongly present in relationship to entities throughout the corpus. This could be the case, for instance, for properties of well-studied organisms such as Drosophila melanogaster or Escherichia coli compared to lesser-studied ones. In our analyses, we did not seek to investigate the lifeness at the level of specific species but adopted a much coarser-grained perspective (bacteria, archaea, viruses etc.). Such a perspective contributes to averaging out such possible biases and to justifying our second premise.
One of the reasons for choosing the BioMed Central collection was its open-access availability for text-mining via a dedicated API, as well as its diversified content in biology-related journals in which we had strong reasons to suspect that the target entities we were interested in would be mentioned. See also discussion in Sect. 7.
In short, this metric measures the distance between the average vector that represents the set of topics belonging to a given category, and the vector that represents a given entity in the semantic vector space constructed on the basis of the corpus. Note that this approach neutralizes—to a certain extent—possible biases due to the differing frequencies with which the target entities are mentioned throughout the corpus: what matters is how often entities and categories are jointly present in the same text excerpts (paragraphs), independently of how often entities are present in the corpus.
One anonymous referee pointed to us a risk of circularity, lifeness scores being assessed along dimensions that refer to humans, plants and animals, which are themselves living systems. But this circularity is only apparent: lifeness scores along these dimensions do not depend on whether we consider humans, plants or animals alive or not. What matters is the extent to which entities—whose lifeness is to be assessed—interact or not with other entities that are labeled humans, plants or animals, independently of whether humans, plants or animals are themselves considered alive or not. A second concern is whether our approach might be too much based on life-as-we-know-it, in its existing context. As a result, lifeness dimensions and scores would change depending on the properties of newly-found entities (e.g. Martian bacteria) or on modifications in the environment (e.g. humans being present or not, as captured by dimension F). We do not see this as a problem: the best perspective we can have on lifeness, we argue, is one that emerges from the scientific practice in its recent state (hence without Martian bacteria and with humans around). Yet, as the state of science changes, lifeness may also change (Martian bacteria might be discovered that have unheard-of properties or humans may go extinct while robots still pursue the project of assessing lifeness). The methodology we propose makes it possible to include novel entities and contexts, and revise our construal of lifeness by re-running the analyses on updated scientific corpora (see also the discussion in Sect. 7).
The overall lower performance of archaea compared to bacteria could come from two factors. (1) It could be the case that archaea have been less studied than bacteria, and therefore that less is currently known about what archaea do (compared to bacteria); in the future therefore, as publications on archaea increase in number and research themes, one will likely see in increase in archaea lifeness. On the other hand (2), it could be the case that archaea are simply less sophisticated in many respects when compared to bacteria. If this is the case, their relative lifeness compared to bacteria will not change in the future. In any case, one should bear in mind that the entities performance is relative to the current state of knowledge of the scientific community (as sampled by the corpus).
Note that an extension of the methodology to entities more complex than bacteria—for instance unicellular or pluricellular eukaryotes—could place such entities at a higher level of performance than bacteria (extending the methodology would raise a number of practical issues, such as extending the corpus to properly cover the entities in question, but we see no principled reason why it would not work). We would see no problem extending the dimensions in such a way as to reflect this state of affairs, and thereby confer an even stronger degree of lifeness to such organisms, were it to be the case. Note that viruses already score higher than 1 with regards to some dimensions. Here our objective was to undermine the binary assumption (Bi) and to re-engineer the concept of life so as to better capture the existence of different degrees and modes of lifeness as suggested by the current state of science. Hence our focus on entities that can intuitively be characterized as belonging to the grey-zone of lifeness.
Note however that studying lifeness at the level of species may raise other methodological difficulties, in particular linked to the fact that certain species of organisms are more studied than others due to their being model organisms or simply because they are easier to study (e.g. micro-organisms that can be cultivated as opposed to those that cannot), or still because they affect human health or economy. In this respect, adopting a more aggregated level averages out these differences (see also footnote 17).
Imagine a corpus that would have included journals in astronomy or physics, or even on origins of life, synthetic biology or theoretical biology: other topics specific to these disciplines would have emerged (e.g., about ‘stars’, ‘planets’, ‘elementary particles’ or about ‘prebiotic chemistry’, ‘engineered micro-organisms’ or ‘theoretical models’). These additional topics could then result in either creating novel topic-categories or modifying existing ones. Yet one also has to consider whether these new topics are correlated or not to the target entities: while one rarely talks about ‘stars’ and ‘bacteria’ in the same paragraphs, some articles may consider ‘microbial contamination’ in the context of space exploration or investigate ‘genetically engineered properties’ of bacteria. Hence the possibility for novel topics to influence the lifeness space.
Interestingly, adding texts that specifically focus on the question of defining life is unlikely to affect the results. Indeed, such texts typically weigh the relative significance of different criteria for life, yet rarely mention target entities. As a result, few of their paragraphs would be retained.
References
Aggarwal, C. C. (2015). Data mining: The textbook. Berlin: Springer.
Arthur, D., & Vassilvitskii, S. (2007). K-means++: The advantages of careful seeding. In Proceedings of the eighteenth annual ACM-SIAM symposium on discrete algorithms, 1027–1035. Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics.
Ashkenasy, G., Jagasia, R., Yadav, M., & Ghadiri, M. R. (2004). Design of a directed molecular network. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 101(30), 10872–10877.
Bains, W. (2014). What do we think life is? A simple illustration and its consequences. International Journal of Astrobiology, 13(02), 101–111. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1473550413000281.
Bedau, M. A. (2011). A functional account of degrees of minimal chemical life. Synthese, 185(1), 73–88. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9876-x.
Benner, S. A. (2010). Defining life. Astrobiology, 10(10), 1021–1030. https://doi.org/10.1089/ast.2010.0524.
Bich, L., & Green, S. (2018). Is defining life pointless? Operational definitions at the frontiers of biology. Synthese, 195(9), 3919–3946. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1397-9.
Bitbol, M., & Luisi, P. L. (2004). Autopoiesis with or without cognition: Defining life at its edge. Journal of the Royal Society, Interface, 1(1), 99–107. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2004.0012.
Blain, J. C., & Szostak, J. W. (2014). Progress toward synthetic cells. Annual Review of Biochemistry, 83(1), 615–640. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-biochem-080411-124036.
Boden, M. (1999). Is metabolism necessary? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(2), 231–248. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/50.2.231.
Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher Taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Brun, G. (2016). Explication as a method of conceptual re-engineering. Erkenntnis, 81(6), 1211–1241. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9791-5.
Bruylants, G., Bartik, K., & Reisse, J. (2010). Is it useful to have a clear-cut definition of life? On the use of fuzzy logic in prebiotic chemistry. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 137–143. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11084-010-9192-3.
Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013a). Conceptual ethics I: Conceptual ethics I. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1091–1101. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12086.
Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013b). Conceptual ethics II: Conceptual ethics II. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1102–1110. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12085.
Cairns-Smith, A. G. (1982). Genetic takeover and the mineral origins of life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cappelen, H. (2018). Fixing language: An essay on conceptual engineering (1st ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Cleland, C. E., & Chyba, C. F. (2007). Does ‘life’ have a definition? In W. T. Sullivan III & J. A. Baross (Eds.), Planets and life: The emerging science of astrobiology (pp. 119–131). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
De Duve, C. (2005). The onset of selection. Nature, 433, 581–582.
Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin's dangerous idea. Evolution and the meaning of life. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Diéguez, A. (2013). Life as a homeostatic property cluster. Biological Theory, 7(2), 180–186. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0052-4.
Dimmock, N., Easton, A., & Leppard, K. (2009). Introduction to modern virology. London: Wiley.
Duhr, S., & Braun, D. (2006). Why molecules move along a temperature gradient. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 103(52), 19678–19682. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0603873103.
Dupré, J., & O’Malley, M. A. (2009). Varieties of living things: Life at the intersection of lineage and metabolism. Philosophy & Theory in Biology, 1, e003.
Eigen, M. (1992). Steps towards life: A perspective on evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eklund, M. (2015). Intuitions, conceptual engineering, and conceptual fixed points. In C. Daly The Palgrave handbook of philosophical methods, pp. 363–385.
Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
England, J. L. (2013). Statistical physics of self-replication. The Journal of Chemical Physics, 139(12), 121923. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.4818538.
Ferreira Ruiz, M. J., & Umerez, J. (2018). ‘Dealing with the changeable and blurry edges of living things: A modified version of property-cluster kinds’. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(3), 493–518. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-018-0210-z.
Firth, J. R. 1957. “A synopsis of linguistic theory 1930–1955.” In Studies in linguistic analysis, pp. 1–32. Oxford: Blackwell.
Forterre, P. (2006). The origin of viruses and their possible roles in major evolutionary transitions. Virus Research, 117(1), 5–16.
Forterre, P. (2010). Defining life: The virus viewpoint. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 151–160. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11084-010-9194-1.
Galperin, M. Y., Makarova, K. S., Wolf, Y. I., & Koonin, E. V. (2015). Expanded microbial genome coverage and improved protein family annotation in the COG database. Nucleic Acids Research, 43(Database issue), D261–D269. https://doi.org/10.1093/nar/gku1223.
Gánti, T. (2003). The principles of life. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, W. (1986). Origin of life: The RNA world. Nature, 319(6055), 618.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.
Griesemer, J. (2003). The philosophical significance of Gánti′s work. In T. Gánti (Ed.), The principle of life (pp. 169–194). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hazen, R. M. (2005). Genesis: The scientific quest for life’s origin. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press.
Hutchison, C. A., Peterson, S. N., Gill, S. R., Cline, R. T., White, O., Fraser, C. M., et al. (1999). Global transposon mutagenesis and a minimal mycoplasma genome. Science, 286(5447), 2165–2169.
Joyce, G. F. (1994). Foreword. In D. W. Deamer & G. R. Fleischaker (Eds.), Origins of life: The central concepts (pp. 11–12). Oxford: Jones and Barlett.
Justus, J. (2012). Carnap on concept determination: Methodology for philosophy of science. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(2), 161–179. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0027-5.
Khalidi, M. A. (1998). Natural kinds and crosscutting categories. The Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 33–50.
Kitcher, P. (2008). Carnap and the caterpillar. Philosophical Topics, 36(1), 111–127.
Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2017). What are definitions of life good for? Transdisciplinary and other definitions in astrobiology. Biology and Philosophy, 32(6), 1185–1203. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9600-4.
Koshland, D. E. (2002). The seven pillars of life. Science, 295(5563), 2215–2216.
Lange, M. (1996). Life, ‘artificial life’, and scientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 225–244.
La Scola, B., Desnues, C., Pagnier, I., Robert, C., Barrassi, L., Fournous, G., et al. (2008). The virophage as a unique parasite of the giant mimivirus. Nature, 455(7209), 100–104. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature07218.
Lederberg, J. (1960). Exobiology: Approaches to life beyond the earth. Science, 132(3424), 393–400. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.132.3424.393.
Lincoln, T. A., & Joyce, G. F. (2009). Self-sustained replication of an RNA enzyme. Science, 323(5918), 1229–1232. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1167856.
Luisi, P. L. (1998). About various definitions of life. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 28(4–6), 613–622.
Luisi, P. L. (2006). The emergence of life: from chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life… and why you should as well. Synthese, 185(1), 145–164. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9880-1.
Machery, E. (2016). Experimental philosophy of science. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 473–490). London: Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118661666.ch33.
Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy within its proper bounds. New York: Oxford University Press.
Madigan, M. T. (2015). Brock biology of microorganisms (14th ed.). Boston: Pearson.
Maher, P. (2007). Explication defended. Studia Logica, 86(2), 331–341. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11225-007-9063-8.
Malaterre, C. (2010a). Les origines de la vie: émergence ou explication réductive?. Paris: Hermann.
Malaterre, C. (2010b). Lifeness signatures and the roots of the tree of life. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 643–658. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9220-8.
Malaterre, C. (2010c). On what it is to fly can tell us something about what it is to live. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 169–177. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11084-010-9196-z.
Malaterre, C. (2013). Microbial diversity and the lower-limit problem of biodiversity. Biology and Philosophy, 28, 219–239.
Mariscal, C., & Doolittle, W. F. (2018). Life and life only: A radical alternative to life definitionism. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1852-2.
Martin, W., & Russell, M. J. (2003). On the origins of cells: A hypothesis for the evolutionary transitions from abiotic geochemistry to chemoautotrophic prokaryotes, and from prokaryotes to nucleated cells. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 358(1429), 59–85. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2002.1183.
Mix, L. J. (2015). Defending definitions of life. Astrobiology, 15(1), 15–19. https://doi.org/10.1089/ast.2014.1191.
Moreira, D., & López-García, P. (2009). Ten reasons to exclude viruses from the tree of life. Nature Reviews Microbiology, 7(4), 306–311.
Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological autonomy, vol. 12. History, philosophy and theory of the life sciences. Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9837-2.
Morowitz, H. J. (1992). Beginnings of cellular life: Metabolism recapitulates biogenesis. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Nakabachi, A., Yamashita, A., Toh, H., Ishikawa, H., Dunbar, H. E., Moran, N. A., et al. (2006). The 160-kilobase genome of the bacterial endosymbiont carsonella. Science, 314(5797), 267. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1134196.
Nghe, P., Hordijk, W., Kauffman, S. A., Walker, S. I., Schmidt, F. J., Kemble, H., et al. (2015). Prebiotic network evolution: Six key parameters. Molecular BioSystems, 11(12), 3206–3217.
Norman, A., Hansen, L. H., & Sørensen, S. J. (2009). Conjugative plasmids: Vessels of the communal gene pool. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1527), 2275–2289.
Palacci, J., Sacanna, S., Steinberg, A. P., Pine, D. J., & Chaikin, P. M. (2013). Living crystals of light-activated colloidal surfers. Science, 339(6122), 936–940. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1230020.
Pályi, G., Zucchi, C., & Caglioti, L. (2002). Fundamentals of life. Paris: Elsevier.
Pirie, N. W. (1937). The meaninglessness of the terms life and living. In J. Needham & D. E. Green (Eds.), Perspectives in biochemistry (pp. 11–22). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Popa, R. (2004). Between necessity and probability: Searching for the definition and origin of life (Vol. 2). Berlin: Springer.
Prigogine, L., Nicolis, G., & Babloyantz, A. (1972). Thermodynamics of evolution. Physics Today, 25(12), 38–44. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.3071140.
Prusiner, S. B. (1982). Novel proteinaceous infectious particles cause scrapie. Science, 216(4542), 136–144.
Raoult, D. (2004). The 1.2-megabase genome sequence of mimivirus. Science, 306(5700), 1344–1350. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1101485.
Raulin, F. (2010). Searching for an exo-life in the solar system. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 191–193. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11084-010-9199-9.
Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: Autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34(3), 323–346.
Saunders, K., & Stanley, J. (1999). A nanovirus-like DNA component associated with yellow vein disease of ageratum conyzoides: Evidence for interfamilial recombination between plant DNA viruses. Virology, 264(1), 142–152.
Schupbach, J. N. (2017). Experimental explication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 94(3), 672–710. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12207.
Schuster, P. (1984). Evolution between chemistry and biology. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 14(1), 3–14.
Seager, S., Bains, W., & Petkowski, J. J. (2016). Toward a list of molecules as potential biosignature gases for the search for life on exoplanets and applications to terrestrial biochemistry. Astrobiology, 16(6), 465–485. https://doi.org/10.1089/ast.2015.1404.
Segré, D., Ben-Eli, D., Deamer, D. W., & Lancet, D. (2001). The lipid world. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 31(1–2), 119–145.
Shepherd, J., & Justus, J. (2015). X-phi and carnapian explication. Erkenntnis, 80(2), 381–402. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9648-3.
Smith, K. C. (2016). Life is hard: Countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. International Journal of Astrobiology, 15(04), 277–289. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1473550416000021.
Smith, J. M., & Szathmáry, E. (1997). The major transitions in evolution. Oxford: OUP.
Tirard, S., Morange, M., & Lazcano, A. (2010). The definition of life: A brief history of an elusive scientific endeavor. Astrobiology, 10(10), 1003–1009.
Trifonov, E. N. (2011). Vocabulary of definitions of life suggests a definition. Journal of Biomolecular Structure & Dynamics, 29(2), 259–266.
Acknowledgements
Access to the BioMed Central Collection is gratefully acknowledged. The authors thank Marc Bedau, Mark Ereshefsky, Michel Morange, Kepa Ruiz-Mirazo and Eran Tal for comments on earlier versions or parts of the manuscript. They also thank the audience of the 2015 “Origins” conference organized by COST Action TD 1308, as well as the participants to the UQAM and McGill 2017 conferences where this work was presented. Thanks are also extended to three anonymous reviewers for Synthese for thoughtful suggestions. Research conducted with funding from Canada Research Chair Program (Grant 950-230795), Canada Foundation for Innovation (Grant 34555), and Canada Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council (Grant 430-2018-00899).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Electronic supplementary material
Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Malaterre, C., Chartier, JF. Beyond categorical definitions of life: a data-driven approach to assessing lifeness. Synthese 198, 4543–4572 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02356-w
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02356-w
Keywords
- Definition of life
- Lifeness space
- Topic-modeling
- Text-mining
- Experimental philosophy of science
- Concept explication