Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Artifacts and affordances

  • S.I.: Between Vision and Action
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What are the affordances of artifacts? One view is that the affordances of artifacts, just as the affordances of natural objects, pertain to possible ways in which they can be manipulated (e.g., a computer keyboard affords grasping). Another view maintains that, given that artifacts are sociocultural objects, their affordances pertain primarily to their culturally-derived function (e.g., a computer keyboard affords typing). Whereas some have tried to provide a unifying notion of affordance to capture both aspects, here I argue that they should be kept separate. In this paper, I introduce a distinction between standard affordances, which concern the function of artifacts, and ad-hoc affordances, which refer to how artifacts are manipulated. I then argue for the neuropsychological plausibility of such a distinction, linking it to the dissociation between function knowledge and manipulation knowledge. Finally, I defend the equal status of these forms of knowledge and, hence, of standard and ad-hoc affordances, and I show that this has some implications for the debate on the role of motor processes in the conceptual knowledge of artifacts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Heft (1989) defines affordances as dispositional properties of the environment relative to the size of some relevant body feature. His definition is based on the results of the classical empirical study by Warren (1984) on stair climbing affordances, which shows that participants’ judgements about whether or not they could climb the stairs without using their arms or legs are based on a constant ratio between riser height and leg length (this ratio, 0.88, is called by Warren “body-scaled” information).

  2. I do not mean to imply here that declarative knowledge is only of verbal nature. My claim is rather that humans are often capable of making verbal statements on the basis of this knowledge. This is fully consistent with the idea of non-verbal declarative knowledge; e.g., non-human animals may possess declarative knowledge about their environment and their conspecific and express it non-verbally.

  3. Declarative and procedural knowledge need not be of different nature or involve different representational formats. See Sect. 2.1 for further discussion of similar issues. See also Pezzullo (2011) for an account of procedural and declarative knowledge in which they are defined, respectively, as on-line sensorimotor anticipation and off-line simulations of potential actions.

  4. Here and elsewhere in the paper, I discuss the notion of “affordance” drawing some analogies to the notion of “function.” However, as I should make clear with the following discussion, the analogy is restricted only to standard affordances and does not extend to ad-hoc affordances. This has two main implications. First, the relation between standard affordances and functions is not clear-cut. My analysis is consistent with the interpretation that standard affordances are, indeed, functions, that is, they are ontologically the same. Second, given that I emphasize the distinction between standard and ad-hoc affordances, and ad-hoc affordances are not functions, I claim that the notion of “affordance” should not be conflated with that of “function.”

  5. In this respect, the notion of standard affordance is similar to that of canonical affordance introduced by Costall (2012). However, I prefer the current term for two reasons. First, the term “canonical affordance” has been used with different meanings in the philosophical and psychological literature. For example, Borghi and Riggio (2009) use this term to refer to something radically different from what is meant by Costall (2012): in their account, canonical affordances are a subset of temporary affordances and are related to the typical orientation with which we interact with objects—for example, the typical orientation with which we read a book. Second, the adjective “canonical” has become popular in the neuroscientific literature to refer to a class of neurons in the F5 area of the premotor cortex of macaque monkey, which discharge during motor act execution and during simple visual presentation of objects (Rizzolatti and Fadiga 1998; Rizzolatti and Umiltà 2013). Thus, the term “canonical affordances” might be misleading, because it might suggest a special relation to canonical neurons. Exploring the relation between canonical neurons and different types of affordances is beyond the scope of this paper.

  6. This phrasing is consistent with the possibility that in a certain given situation, standard affordances might not be appropriately detected. For example, a mailbox does not afford sending correspondence if it is pulled away and lying on the ground. Still, we would maintain that mailboxes do generally afford sending correspondence. The concept of a mailbox seems to include what mailboxes are generally for, that is, what type of function is usually supported by them.

  7. The paper is neutral with respect to this issue. In fact, a crucial claim of the paper is that it is not necessary to put this issue at stake to address the question of the role of motor processes in the conceptual knowledge of artifacts. See Sect. 3 for a detailed argument in support of this claim.

  8. For example, at an elegant cocktail party, it might be socially inappropriate for a particular agent to stand on the buffet table. This particular ad-hoc affordance is, then, very unlikely to be selected by the agent in that context.

  9. Even though Garcea and Mahon phrase their claim in terms of the necessity of function knowledge for the possession of a minimal concept of an artifact, their discussion of apraxic patients (see below in the text) seems to involve that function knowledge is even sufficient for a minimal concept possession. However, they are careful not to phrase their hypothesis this way, so the following discussion will only assume the requirement of necessity. Whether or not the notion of a minimal or core concept is an adequate one, will remain on the background of the current discussion. For the sake of the argument, I will assume that this notion is adequate, however it should be noted that it is not unproblematic. Pulvermüller (2013) has pointed out to a number of criticisms concerning this notion in his discussion of the idea, presented by Mahon and Caramazza (2008) and Bedny and Caramazza (2011), that the functional contribution of sensorimotor systems to conceptual or semantic processing would consist in enriching (“coloring” and “dressing”, Mahon and Caramazza 2008, p. 68f) the conceptual representation.

  10. It should be noted, though, that apraxic patients have been found to be able to associate an appropriate hand posture to novel objects, but not to familiar objects (Buxbaum et al. 2003). Thus, manipulation knowledge might be compromised in apraxic patients only for familiar objects, but not for novel objects.

  11. The Grounding by Interaction Hypothesis holds that there is a level of conceptual content which is “abstract” or “symbolic”, that is, not constituted by sensory and motor information. However, sensorimotor systems functionally contribute to conceptual processing by “coloring” or “dressing” the concept (Mahon and Caramazza 2008, p. 68f; see also note 10 above).

References

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedny, M., & Caramazza, A. (2011). Perception, action, and word meanings in the human brain: The case from action verbs. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1224, 81–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. M., & Riggio, L. (2009). Sentence comprehension and simulation of objects temporary, canonical and stable affordances. Brain Research, 1253, 117–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boronat, C. B., Buxbaum, L. J., Coslett, H. B., Tang, K., Saffran, E. M., Kimberg, D. Y., et al. (2005). Distinctions between manipulation and function knowledge of objects: Evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging. Cognitive Brain Research, 23, 361–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., & Saffran, E. M. (2002). Knowledge of object manipulation and object function: Dissociations in apraxic and non-apraxic subjects. Brain and Language, 82, 179–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Schwartz, M. F., & Carew, T. (1997). The role of semantic memory in object use. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 14, 219–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Sirigu, A., Schwartz, M. F., & Klatzky, R. (2003). Cognitive representations of hand posture in ideomotor apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 41, 1091–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Veramonti, T., & Schwartz, M. F. (2000). Function and manipulation tool knowledge in apraxia: Knowing “what for” but not “how”. Neurocase, 6, 83–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capitani, E., Laiacona, M., Mahon, B., & Caramazza, A. (2003). What are the facts of semantic category-specific deficits? A critical review of the clinical evidence. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 20, 213–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2003). An outline of a theory of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 181–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosentino, E., Baggio, G., Kontinen, J., & Werning, M. (2017). The time-course of sentence meaning composition. N400 effects of the interaction between context-induced and lexically stored affordances. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (2012). Canonical affordances in context. Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies, 3(2), 85–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cubelli, R., Marchetti, C., Boscolo, G., & Della, Salla S. (2000). Cognition in action: Testing a model of limb apraxia. Brain and Cognition, 44, 144–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. The Journal of Philosophy, 72(20), 741–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, J., Russell, R., Davis, M., Price, C., Moss, H., Fadili, M., et al. (2002). Is there an anatomical basis for category-specificity? Semantic memory studies in PET and fMRI. Neuropsychologia, 40, 54–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, R., & Tucker, M. (2000). Micro-affordance: The potentiation of components of action by seen objects. British Journal of Psychology, 91, 451–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22, 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcea, F. E., & Mahon, B. Z. (2012). What is in a tool concept? Dissociating manipulation knowledge from function knowledge. Memory and Cognition, 40(8), 1303–1313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerlach, C., Law, I., Gade, A., & Paulson, O. B. (1999). Perceptual differentiation and category effects in normal object recognition: A PET study. Brain, 122, 2159–2170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. (1999). Why mental models must be embodied. Advances in Psychology, 128, 77–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M., & Robertson, D. A. (2000). Symbol grounding and meaning: A comparison of high dimensional and embodied theories of meaning. Journal of Memory and Language, 43, 379–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink, R. (2016). The metaphysics of cognitive artefacts. Philosophical Explorations, 19(1), 78–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heft, H. (1989). Affordances and the body: An intentional analysis of Gibson’s ecological approach to visual perception. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 19, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W. (2006). Knowledge of artefact functions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 37(1), 102–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W., & Vermaas, P. E. (2010). Technical functions: On the use and design of artefacts (Vol. 1). Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kellenbach, M., Brett, M., & Patterson, K. (2003). Actions speak louder than functions: The importance of manipulability and action in tool representation. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 15, 30–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutas, M., & Federmeier, K. D. (2011). Thirty years and counting: Finding meaning in the N400 component of the event-related brain potential (ERP). Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 621–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambon-Ralph, M. A., Howard, D., Nightingale, G., & Ellis, A. W. (1998). Are living and non-living category-specific deficits causally linked to impaired perceptual or associative knowledge? Evidence from a category-specific double dissociation. Neurocase, 4, 311–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leiguarda, R. C., & Marsden, C. D. (2000). Limb apraxias: Higher-order disorders of sensorimotor integration. Brain, 123, 860–879.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liepmann, H. (1977). The syndrome of apraxia (motor asymboly) based on a case of unilateral apraxia. (A translation from Monatschrift für Psychiatrie und Neurologie). In D. A. Rottenberg & F. H. Hockberg (Eds.), Neurological classics in modern translation (Vol. 8, pp. 15–44). New York: Macmillan Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnie, M. N., Teixeira Ferreira, C., Giusiano, B., & Poncet, M. (1999). Category specificity in object agnosia: Preservation of sensorimotor experiences related to objects. Neuropsychologia, 37, 67–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2005). The orchestration of the sensory-motor systems: Clues from neuropsychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22, 480–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2008). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology – Paris, 102(1–3), 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2009). Concepts and categories: A cognitive neuropsychological perspective. Annual Reviews in Psychology, 60, 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2011). What drives the organization of object knowledge in the brain? Trends In Cognitive Science, 15, 97–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, C. J., & Price, C. J. (1999). A functional neuroimaging study of the variables that generate category-specific object processing differences. Brain, 122, 943–962.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negri, G. A., Lunardelli, A., Reverberi, C., Gigli, G. L., & Rumiati, R. I. (2007). Degraded semantic knowledge and accurate object use. Cerebral Cortex, 43, 376–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, D. (1999). Affordance, conventions and design. Interactions, 5, 38–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pezzullo, G. (2011). Grounding procedural and declarative knowledge in sensorimotor anticipation. Mind and Language, 26(1), 78–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, B. (1998). Why is a wing like a spoon, a pluralist theory of function. The Journal of Philosophy, 95(5), 215–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulvermüller, F. (2013). Semantic embodiment, disembodiment or misembodiment? In search of meaning in modules and neuron circuits. Brain and Language, 127, 86–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, E. S. (1996). Encountering the world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Fadiga, L. (1998). Grasping objects and grasping action meanings: The dual role of monkey rostroventral premotor cortex (area F5). Sensory Guidance of Movement, 218, 81–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Umiltà, M. A. (2013). Canonical neurons. In A. L. C. Runehov & L. Oviedo (Eds.), Encyclopedia of sciences and religions. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothi, L. J. G., Ochipam, C., & Heilman, K. M. (1991). A cognitive neuropsychological model of limb praxis. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 8, 443–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacchett, C., & Humphreys, G. W. (1992). Calling a squirrel a squirrel but a canoe a wigwam: A category-specific deficit for artifactual objects and body parts. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 9, 73–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, R., Turvey, M., & Mace, W. (1982). Ecological psychology: The consequence of a commitment to realism. In W. Weimer & D. Palermo (Eds.), Cognition and the symbolic processes (pp. 159–226). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sirigu, A. J., Duhamel, J. R., & Poncet, M. (1991). The role of sensorimotor experience in object recognition. Brain, 114, 2555–2573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson-Schill, S. (2003). Neuroimaging studies of semantic memory: Inferring “how” from “where”. Neuropsychologia, 41, 280–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, M., & Ellis, R. (1998). On the relations between seen objects and components of potential actions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 24(3), 830–846.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, M., & Ellis, R. (2001). The potentiation of grasp types during visual object categorization. Visual Cognition, 8, 769–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. (1992). Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology. Ecological Psychology, 4, 173–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W. H. (1984). Perceiving affordances: Visual guidance of stair climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Performance and Perception, 10, 683–703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warrington, E. K., & McCarthy, R. (1983). Category specific access dysphasia. Brain, 106, 859–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warrington, E. K., & McCarthy, R. A. (1987). Categories of knowledge. Further fractionations and an attempted integration. Brain, 110, 1273–1296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warrington, E. K., & Shallice, T. (1984). Category specific semantic impairments. Brain, 107, 829–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1974). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82(2), 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research has been presented at the 24th Annual Meeting of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology (ESPP) in St. Andrews, at the CoSt2016 in Düsseldorf, and in the research colloquium of the Mercator Research Group “Structure of Memory.” I would like to thank the participants in these events for their helpful comments. Also, I thank the colleagues who contributed to this research with their valuable insights, in particular, Anna M. Borghi, Francesco Ferretti, and Markus Werning.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erica Cosentino.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cosentino, E. Artifacts and affordances. Synthese 198 (Suppl 17), 4007–4026 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02297-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02297-4

Keywords

Navigation