Skip to main content
Log in

Does the temporal asymmetry of value support a tensed metaphysics?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are temporal asymmetries in our attitudes towards the past and future. For example, we judge that a given amount of work is worth twice as much if it is described as taking place in the future, compared to the past (Caruso et al. in Psychol Sci 19(8):796–801, 2008). Does this temporal value asymmetry support a tensed metaphysics? By getting clear on the asymmetry’s features, I’ll argue that it doesn’t. To support a tensed metaphysics, the value asymmetry would need to (a) not vary with temporal distance, (b) apply equally to events concerning oneself and others, and (c) be rational and judged to be so. But evidence suggests the value asymmetry lacks these features. There are, moreover, independent arguments against its rationality. The asymmetry’s features suggest instead that it arises as an emotion-driven generalisation from a temporal bias concerning our future actions. This explanation points towards mechanisms that can play a role in explaining other instances where we generalise about the past and future, and why we’re tempted towards metaphysical pictures of time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The asymmetry is replicated in Guo et al. (2012) and Burns et al. (2018). These studies are discussed in Sects. 3 and 4.

  2. I’ll follow Caruso et al. (2008) in treating these cases similarly, but further investigation could show they are distinct.

  3. The value asymmetry implies a preference asymmetry, given other assumptions. Roughly, valuing a good future event more (rationally) implies being willing to swap a good future event for more now than one would swap an equivalent past event, indicating a preference for good things to be in the future and, mutatis mutandi, bad things to be in the past. See Dougherty (2015) for why preference and value asymmetries may not manifest in the same circumstances.

  4. Views that deny non-relative tensed facts while still accepting a primitive direction of time (Maudlin 2007) count as B-theoretic with respect to these arguments.

  5. One might argue that values can be relativised to times, without being relativised to subjective features. However, what time-relative value is relevant to a given subject will still depend on when she is located. So value will still seem worryingly subjective (to the objectivist).

  6. While value and preference asymmetries are distinct (see footnote 3), results in both cases suggest that our asymmetric behaviour can’t be accounted for using merely a tensed metaphysics.

  7. Caution is required in interpreting these results. With the exception of Radu et al. (2011), the future and past questions may have been intermingled. If so, past discounting may simply be an artifact of future discounting. There are also difficult questions regarding how preferences regarding past events are to be interpreted—I discuss some of these issues below (Sect. 3.3).

  8. Is the asymmetry nevertheless rational? Hare (2007, 2008), and Parfit (1984, pp. 165–167) and Tarsney (2017) argue for the prima facie rationality of preference asymmetries. Others disagree. Sullivan (2018, Ch. 7) argues that preference asymmetries are arbitrary. Dougherty (2011) argues that someone with temporally biased preferences will be led to accept a series of swaps that leaves her worse off overall. Greene and Sullivan (2015), see also Sullivan (Ch. 6, 2018), argue that someone with temporally biased preferences will be led to unreasonably delay pleasures. For criticisms of Dougherty and Sullivan’s arguments, see Hare (2013), Greene and Sullivan (2015), Dorsey (2016) and Tarsney (2017). For criticism of Parfit and discussion of other arguments for temporal neutrality, see Brink (2011).

  9. For more on the emotion asymmetry and the role of emotion in choice, see Newby-Clark and Ross (2003), van Boven and Ashworth (2007) and Gilbert and Wilson (2009). Guo et al. (2012) argue that the value asymmetry is also affected by cultural orientation. Note that acknowledging various higher-level effects on the value asymmetry is compatible with the philosophical points regarding ‘generalising’ that I go on to make.

  10. For example, generalising is required to explain why we bet more optimistically on the future than the past (Strickland et al. 1966), why we judge future actions as more due to the will (Helzer and Gilovich 2012), why we judge past transgressions less harshly (Caruso 2010), and why we judge that future events feel closer (Van Caruso et al. 2013).

  11. We also form more extreme expectations about how we’ll feel in the future (Miloyan and Suddendorf 2015). Van Boven and Ashworth (2007) argue, however, that this is a minimal contributor to the emotion asymmetry.

  12. While essences often concern immutable features of events, this is not always the case—such as when we essentialise about people’s age (Weiss et al. 2016). Similarly, even though events change from being future to being past, their properties now can still be attributable to essential features of past or future events.

References

  • Albert, D. (2015). After physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickel, W. K., Yi, R., Kowal, B. P., & Gatchalian, K. M. (2008). Cigarette smokers discount past and future rewards symmetrically and more than controls: Is discounting a measure of impulsivity? Drug and Alcohol Dependence, 96(3), 256–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchard, T. (2014). Causation in a physical world. PhD Thesis. Rutgers University.

  • Brink, D. O. (2011). Prospects for temporal neutrality. In Craig Callender (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buehler, R., Griffin, D., & Ross, M. (1994). Exploring the “planning fallacy”: Why people underestimate their task completion times. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 366–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, Z. C., Caruso, E. M., & Bartels, D. M. (2012). Predicting premeditation: Future behavior is seen as more intentional than past behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 141, 227–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, P., McCormack, T., & Lee, R. (2018). A developmental perspective on temporal asymmetries. In Presentation at temporal asymmetries in philosophy and psychology workshop, University of Warwick.

  • Burns, P., McCormack, T., Jaroslawska, A., Fitzpatrick, A., McGourty, J., & Caruso, E. M. (2019). The development of asymmetries in past and future thinking. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 148(2), 272–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caouette, J., Wohl, M. J. A., & Peetz, J. (2012). The future weighs heavier than the past: Collective guilt, perceived control and the influence of time. European Journal of Social Psychology., 42, 363–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, E. M. (2010). When the future feels worse than the past: A temporal inconsistency in moral judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 139(4), 610–624.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, E. M., Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2008). A wrinkle in time: Asymmetric valuation of past and future events. Psychological Science, 19(8), 796–801.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, E. M., Van Boven, L., Chin, M., & Ward, A. (2018). Why the future is bigger (and “Badder”) than the past. Presentation at temporal asymmetries in philosophy and psychology workshop, University of Warwick.

  • Cimpian, A., & Salomon, E. (2014). The inherence heuristic: An intuitive means of making sense of the world, and a potential precursor to psychological essentialism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 461–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cockburn, D. (1998). Tense and emotion. In R. Le Poidevin (Ed.), Questions of time and tense (pp. 77–91). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. (2000). The tensed theory of time. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Argembeau, A., & van der Linden, M. (2004). Phenomenal characteristics associated with projecting oneself back into the past and forward into the future: Influence of valence and temporal distance. Consciousness and Cognition, 13, 844–858.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, M. R., & Holton, B. (2009). Altering the magnitude of delay discounting by pathological gamblers. Journal of Applied Behavioral Analysis., 42, 269–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsey, D. (2016). Future-bias: A (qualified) defense. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T. (2011). On whether to prefer pain to pass. Ethics, 121(3), 521–537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T. (2015). Future-bias and practical reason. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(30), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandes, A. (2017). A deliberative approach to causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 95(3), 686–708.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandes, A. (2018). Freedom, self-prediction, and the possibility of time travel. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1181-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40(2), 351–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2009). Why the brain talks to itself: Sources of error in emotional prediction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B., 364, 1335–1341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, S. A., Kilbreath, C. S., & Welder, A. N. (2004). Thirteen-month-olds rely on shared labels and shape similarity for inductive inferences. Child Development, 75(2), 409–427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, P., Latham, A., Miller, K., & Norton, J. (2019). Hedonic and non-hedonic bias towards the future. Unpublished manuscript. https://static1.squarespace.com/static/56d45b30f699bb6f0beeaf5a/t/5c42db2d21c67cc78da93757/1547885361222/Greene+et+al%2C+Hedonic+and+Non-Hedonic+Bias+Toward+the+Future.pdf. Accessed 24 Feb 2019.

  • Greene, P., & Sullivan, M. (2015). Against time bias. Ethics, 125, 947–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guo, T., Ji, L.-J., Spina, R., & Zhang, Z. (2012). Culture, temporal focus, and values of the past and the future. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(8), 1030–1040.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, C. (2007). Self-bias, time-bias, and the metaphysics of self and time. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(7), 350–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, C. (2008). A puzzle about other-directed time-bias. Australasian Journal of Philosophy., 86(2), 269–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, C. (2013). Time—The emotional asymmetry. In Heather Dyke & Adrian Bardon (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of time. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • He, J. M., Huang, X. T., Yuan, H., & Chen, Y. G. (2012). Neural activity in relation to temporal distance: Differences in past and future temporal discounting. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(4), 1662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helzer, E. G., & Gilovich, T. (2012). Whatever is willed will be: A temporal asymmetry in attributions to will. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(10), 1235–1246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2015). Tense and the psychology of relief. Topoi, 34(1), 217–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1987). Asymmetries in time. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2016). How physics makes us free. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, J., Van Boven, L., & McGraw, A. P. (2012). Prototypical prospection: Future events are more prototypically represented and simulated than past events. European Journal of Social Psychology, 42(3), 354–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, R., McCormack, T., Burns, P., O’Connor, P. A., Fernandes, A. S., & Hoerl, C. (2018). The development of a past-future temporal value asymmetry for hedonic goods. Presentation at European Society for Philosophy and Psychology, Rijeka.

  • Maclaurin, J., & Dyke, H. (2002). ‘Thank goodness that’s over’: The evolutionary story. Ratio, 15(3), 276–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2008). Temporal decentering and the development of temporal concepts. Language Learning, 58, 89–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D. L., & Ortony, A. (1989). Psychological essentialism. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 179–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1981). Real Time. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1998). Real time II. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miloyan, B., & Suddendorf, T. (2015). Feelings of the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences., 19(4), 196–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newby-Clark, I. R., & Ross, M. (2003). Conceiving the past and future. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 20, 807–818.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, E. (2015). Mapping out past and future minds: The perceived trajectory of rationality versus emotionality over time. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 144(3), 624–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13(1), 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1996). Time’s arrow and archimedes point: New directions for the physics of time. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1959). Thank goodness that’s over. Philosophy, 34(128), 12–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pronin, E., & Ross, L. (2006). Temporal differences in trait self-ascription: When the self is seen as an other. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 197–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prosser, S. (2016). Experiencing time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radu, P. T., Yi, R., Bickel, W. K., Gross, J. J., & McClure, S. M. (2011). A mechanism for reducing delay discounting by altering temporal attention. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 96(3), 363–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes, M., & Mandalaywala, T. M. (2017). The development and developmental consequences of social essentialism. Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 8(4), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roh, S., & Schuldt, J. P. (2014). Where there’s a will: Can highlighting future youth-targeted marketing increase support for soda taxes? Health Psychology, 33(12), 1610–1613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. (1976). The stillness of time and philosophical equanimity. Philosophical Studies, 30(3), 145–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Q. (2002). Time and degrees of existence: A theory of ‘degree presentism’. In C. Callender (Ed.), Time, reality and experience (pp. 119–136). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strickland, L. H., Lewicki, R. J., & Katz, A. M. (1966). Temporal orientation and perceived control as determinants of risk-taking. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 2(2), 143–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suhler, C., & Callender, C. (2012). Thank goodness that argument is over: Explaining the temporal value asymmetry. Philosophers’ Imprint, 12(15), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, M. (2018). A theory of rational planning and personal persistence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarsney, C. (2017). Thank goodness that’s Newcomb: The practical relevance of the temporal value asymmetry. Analysis, 77(4), 750–759.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trope, Y., & Liberman, N. (2003). Temporal construal. Psychological Review, 110(3), 403–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., & Ashworth, L. (2007). Looking forward, looking back: Anticipation is more evocative than retrospection. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 136(2), 289–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., & Caruso, E. M. (2015). The tripartite foundations of temporal psychological distance: Metaphors, ecology, and teleology. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 9(11), 593–605.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., Kane, J., & McGraw, A. P. (2010). Temporally asymmetric constraints on mental simulation: Retrospection is more constrained than prospection. In K. D. Markman, W. M. P. Klein, & J. A. Suhr (Eds.), Handbook of imagination and mental simulation (pp. 131–147). New York, NY: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Caruso, E. M., Boven, L., Chin, M., & Ward, A. (2013). The temporal Doppler effect: When the future feels closer than the past. Psychological Science, 24(4), 530–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, D., Job, V., Mathias, M., Grah, S., & Freund, A. (2016). The end is (not) near: Aging, essentialism, and future time perspective. Developmental Psychology, 52(6), 996–1009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2005). Affective forecasting: Knowing what to want. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14(3), 131–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2008). Explaining away: A model of affective adaptation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 370–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yi, R., Gatchalian, K. M., & Bickel, W. K. (2006). Discounting of past outcomes. Experimental and Clinical Psychopharmacology, 14(3), 311–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, D. W. (2007). The privileged present: Defending an ‘A-theory’ of time. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 211–225). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack, Ruth Lee and Patrick Burns for many helpful discussions, and for including me so enthusiastically in their work. I would also like to thank the following people for comments and suggestions: Meghan Sullivan, Alistair Wilson, Natlja Deng, Nick Jones, Tom Dougherty, Scott Sturgeon, Craig Callender, and Tobias Wilsch, as well as audiences at the University of Warwick, and the University of Birmingham. This work was supported by a Research Fellowship at the University of Warwick on the AHRC project ‘Time: Between Metaphysics and Psychology’ (AH/P00217X/1), Principal Investigator Christoph Hoerl and Co-Investigator Teresa McCormack.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alison Fernandes.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fernandes, A. Does the temporal asymmetry of value support a tensed metaphysics?. Synthese 198, 3999–4016 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02269-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02269-8

Keywords

Navigation