Abstract
There are temporal asymmetries in our attitudes towards the past and future. For example, we judge that a given amount of work is worth twice as much if it is described as taking place in the future, compared to the past (Caruso et al. in Psychol Sci 19(8):796–801, 2008). Does this temporal value asymmetry support a tensed metaphysics? By getting clear on the asymmetry’s features, I’ll argue that it doesn’t. To support a tensed metaphysics, the value asymmetry would need to (a) not vary with temporal distance, (b) apply equally to events concerning oneself and others, and (c) be rational and judged to be so. But evidence suggests the value asymmetry lacks these features. There are, moreover, independent arguments against its rationality. The asymmetry’s features suggest instead that it arises as an emotion-driven generalisation from a temporal bias concerning our future actions. This explanation points towards mechanisms that can play a role in explaining other instances where we generalise about the past and future, and why we’re tempted towards metaphysical pictures of time.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
I’ll follow Caruso et al. (2008) in treating these cases similarly, but further investigation could show they are distinct.
The value asymmetry implies a preference asymmetry, given other assumptions. Roughly, valuing a good future event more (rationally) implies being willing to swap a good future event for more now than one would swap an equivalent past event, indicating a preference for good things to be in the future and, mutatis mutandi, bad things to be in the past. See Dougherty (2015) for why preference and value asymmetries may not manifest in the same circumstances.
Views that deny non-relative tensed facts while still accepting a primitive direction of time (Maudlin 2007) count as B-theoretic with respect to these arguments.
One might argue that values can be relativised to times, without being relativised to subjective features. However, what time-relative value is relevant to a given subject will still depend on when she is located. So value will still seem worryingly subjective (to the objectivist).
While value and preference asymmetries are distinct (see footnote 3), results in both cases suggest that our asymmetric behaviour can’t be accounted for using merely a tensed metaphysics.
Caution is required in interpreting these results. With the exception of Radu et al. (2011), the future and past questions may have been intermingled. If so, past discounting may simply be an artifact of future discounting. There are also difficult questions regarding how preferences regarding past events are to be interpreted—I discuss some of these issues below (Sect. 3.3).
Is the asymmetry nevertheless rational? Hare (2007, 2008), and Parfit (1984, pp. 165–167) and Tarsney (2017) argue for the prima facie rationality of preference asymmetries. Others disagree. Sullivan (2018, Ch. 7) argues that preference asymmetries are arbitrary. Dougherty (2011) argues that someone with temporally biased preferences will be led to accept a series of swaps that leaves her worse off overall. Greene and Sullivan (2015), see also Sullivan (Ch. 6, 2018), argue that someone with temporally biased preferences will be led to unreasonably delay pleasures. For criticisms of Dougherty and Sullivan’s arguments, see Hare (2013), Greene and Sullivan (2015), Dorsey (2016) and Tarsney (2017). For criticism of Parfit and discussion of other arguments for temporal neutrality, see Brink (2011).
For more on the emotion asymmetry and the role of emotion in choice, see Newby-Clark and Ross (2003), van Boven and Ashworth (2007) and Gilbert and Wilson (2009). Guo et al. (2012) argue that the value asymmetry is also affected by cultural orientation. Note that acknowledging various higher-level effects on the value asymmetry is compatible with the philosophical points regarding ‘generalising’ that I go on to make.
For example, generalising is required to explain why we bet more optimistically on the future than the past (Strickland et al. 1966), why we judge future actions as more due to the will (Helzer and Gilovich 2012), why we judge past transgressions less harshly (Caruso 2010), and why we judge that future events feel closer (Van Caruso et al. 2013).
While essences often concern immutable features of events, this is not always the case—such as when we essentialise about people’s age (Weiss et al. 2016). Similarly, even though events change from being future to being past, their properties now can still be attributable to essential features of past or future events.
References
Albert, D. (2015). After physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bickel, W. K., Yi, R., Kowal, B. P., & Gatchalian, K. M. (2008). Cigarette smokers discount past and future rewards symmetrically and more than controls: Is discounting a measure of impulsivity? Drug and Alcohol Dependence, 96(3), 256–262.
Blanchard, T. (2014). Causation in a physical world. PhD Thesis. Rutgers University.
Brink, D. O. (2011). Prospects for temporal neutrality. In Craig Callender (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Buehler, R., Griffin, D., & Ross, M. (1994). Exploring the “planning fallacy”: Why people underestimate their task completion times. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 366–381.
Burns, Z. C., Caruso, E. M., & Bartels, D. M. (2012). Predicting premeditation: Future behavior is seen as more intentional than past behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 141, 227–232.
Burns, P., McCormack, T., & Lee, R. (2018). A developmental perspective on temporal asymmetries. In Presentation at temporal asymmetries in philosophy and psychology workshop, University of Warwick.
Burns, P., McCormack, T., Jaroslawska, A., Fitzpatrick, A., McGourty, J., & Caruso, E. M. (2019). The development of asymmetries in past and future thinking. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 148(2), 272–288.
Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Caouette, J., Wohl, M. J. A., & Peetz, J. (2012). The future weighs heavier than the past: Collective guilt, perceived control and the influence of time. European Journal of Social Psychology., 42, 363–371.
Caruso, E. M. (2010). When the future feels worse than the past: A temporal inconsistency in moral judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 139(4), 610–624.
Caruso, E. M., Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2008). A wrinkle in time: Asymmetric valuation of past and future events. Psychological Science, 19(8), 796–801.
Caruso, E. M., Van Boven, L., Chin, M., & Ward, A. (2018). Why the future is bigger (and “Badder”) than the past. Presentation at temporal asymmetries in philosophy and psychology workshop, University of Warwick.
Cimpian, A., & Salomon, E. (2014). The inherence heuristic: An intuitive means of making sense of the world, and a potential precursor to psychological essentialism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 461–480.
Cockburn, D. (1998). Tense and emotion. In R. Le Poidevin (Ed.), Questions of time and tense (pp. 77–91). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Craig, W. (2000). The tensed theory of time. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
D’Argembeau, A., & van der Linden, M. (2004). Phenomenal characteristics associated with projecting oneself back into the past and forward into the future: Influence of valence and temporal distance. Consciousness and Cognition, 13, 844–858.
Dixon, M. R., & Holton, B. (2009). Altering the magnitude of delay discounting by pathological gamblers. Journal of Applied Behavioral Analysis., 42, 269–275.
Dorsey, D. (2016). Future-bias: A (qualified) defense. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12176.
Dougherty, T. (2011). On whether to prefer pain to pass. Ethics, 121(3), 521–537.
Dougherty, T. (2015). Future-bias and practical reason. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(30), 1–16.
Fernandes, A. (2017). A deliberative approach to causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 95(3), 686–708.
Fernandes, A. (2018). Freedom, self-prediction, and the possibility of time travel. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1181-9
Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40(2), 351–401.
Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2009). Why the brain talks to itself: Sources of error in emotional prediction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B., 364, 1335–1341.
Graham, S. A., Kilbreath, C. S., & Welder, A. N. (2004). Thirteen-month-olds rely on shared labels and shape similarity for inductive inferences. Child Development, 75(2), 409–427.
Greene, P., Latham, A., Miller, K., & Norton, J. (2019). Hedonic and non-hedonic bias towards the future. Unpublished manuscript. https://static1.squarespace.com/static/56d45b30f699bb6f0beeaf5a/t/5c42db2d21c67cc78da93757/1547885361222/Greene+et+al%2C+Hedonic+and+Non-Hedonic+Bias+Toward+the+Future.pdf. Accessed 24 Feb 2019.
Greene, P., & Sullivan, M. (2015). Against time bias. Ethics, 125, 947–970.
Guo, T., Ji, L.-J., Spina, R., & Zhang, Z. (2012). Culture, temporal focus, and values of the past and the future. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(8), 1030–1040.
Hare, C. (2007). Self-bias, time-bias, and the metaphysics of self and time. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(7), 350–373.
Hare, C. (2008). A puzzle about other-directed time-bias. Australasian Journal of Philosophy., 86(2), 269–277.
Hare, C. (2013). Time—The emotional asymmetry. In Heather Dyke & Adrian Bardon (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of time. Chichester: Wiley.
He, J. M., Huang, X. T., Yuan, H., & Chen, Y. G. (2012). Neural activity in relation to temporal distance: Differences in past and future temporal discounting. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(4), 1662.
Helzer, E. G., & Gilovich, T. (2012). Whatever is willed will be: A temporal asymmetry in attributions to will. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(10), 1235–1246.
Hoerl, C. (2015). Tense and the psychology of relief. Topoi, 34(1), 217–231.
Horwich, P. (1987). Asymmetries in time. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Ismael, J. (2016). How physics makes us free. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kane, J., Van Boven, L., & McGraw, A. P. (2012). Prototypical prospection: Future events are more prototypically represented and simulated than past events. European Journal of Social Psychology, 42(3), 354–362.
Lee, R., McCormack, T., Burns, P., O’Connor, P. A., Fernandes, A. S., & Hoerl, C. (2018). The development of a past-future temporal value asymmetry for hedonic goods. Presentation at European Society for Philosophy and Psychology, Rijeka.
Maclaurin, J., & Dyke, H. (2002). ‘Thank goodness that’s over’: The evolutionary story. Ratio, 15(3), 276–292.
Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2008). Temporal decentering and the development of temporal concepts. Language Learning, 58, 89–113.
Medin, D. L., & Ortony, A. (1989). Psychological essentialism. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 179–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mellor, D. H. (1981). Real Time. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Mellor, D. H. (1998). Real time II. London: Routledge.
Miloyan, B., & Suddendorf, T. (2015). Feelings of the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences., 19(4), 196–200.
Newby-Clark, I. R., & Ross, M. (2003). Conceiving the past and future. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 20, 807–818.
O’Brien, E. (2015). Mapping out past and future minds: The perceived trajectory of rationality versus emotionality over time. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 144(3), 624–638.
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13(1), 3–21.
Price, H. (1996). Time’s arrow and archimedes point: New directions for the physics of time. New York: Oxford University Press.
Prior, A. N. (1959). Thank goodness that’s over. Philosophy, 34(128), 12–17.
Pronin, E., & Ross, L. (2006). Temporal differences in trait self-ascription: When the self is seen as an other. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 197–209.
Prosser, S. (2016). Experiencing time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Radu, P. T., Yi, R., Bickel, W. K., Gross, J. J., & McClure, S. M. (2011). A mechanism for reducing delay discounting by altering temporal attention. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 96(3), 363–385.
Rhodes, M., & Mandalaywala, T. M. (2017). The development and developmental consequences of social essentialism. Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 8(4), 1–18.
Roh, S., & Schuldt, J. P. (2014). Where there’s a will: Can highlighting future youth-targeted marketing increase support for soda taxes? Health Psychology, 33(12), 1610–1613.
Scanlon, T. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schlesinger, G. (1976). The stillness of time and philosophical equanimity. Philosophical Studies, 30(3), 145–159.
Smith, Q. (2002). Time and degrees of existence: A theory of ‘degree presentism’. In C. Callender (Ed.), Time, reality and experience (pp. 119–136). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Strickland, L. H., Lewicki, R. J., & Katz, A. M. (1966). Temporal orientation and perceived control as determinants of risk-taking. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 2(2), 143–151.
Suhler, C., & Callender, C. (2012). Thank goodness that argument is over: Explaining the temporal value asymmetry. Philosophers’ Imprint, 12(15), 1–16.
Sullivan, M. (2018). A theory of rational planning and personal persistence. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tarsney, C. (2017). Thank goodness that’s Newcomb: The practical relevance of the temporal value asymmetry. Analysis, 77(4), 750–759.
Trope, Y., & Liberman, N. (2003). Temporal construal. Psychological Review, 110(3), 403–421.
Van Boven, L., & Ashworth, L. (2007). Looking forward, looking back: Anticipation is more evocative than retrospection. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 136(2), 289–300.
Van Boven, L., & Caruso, E. M. (2015). The tripartite foundations of temporal psychological distance: Metaphors, ecology, and teleology. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 9(11), 593–605.
Van Boven, L., Kane, J., & McGraw, A. P. (2010). Temporally asymmetric constraints on mental simulation: Retrospection is more constrained than prospection. In K. D. Markman, W. M. P. Klein, & J. A. Suhr (Eds.), Handbook of imagination and mental simulation (pp. 131–147). New York, NY: Psychology Press.
Van Caruso, E. M., Boven, L., Chin, M., & Ward, A. (2013). The temporal Doppler effect: When the future feels closer than the past. Psychological Science, 24(4), 530–536.
Weiss, D., Job, V., Mathias, M., Grah, S., & Freund, A. (2016). The end is (not) near: Aging, essentialism, and future time perspective. Developmental Psychology, 52(6), 996–1009.
Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2005). Affective forecasting: Knowing what to want. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14(3), 131–134.
Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2008). Explaining away: A model of affective adaptation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 370–386.
Yi, R., Gatchalian, K. M., & Bickel, W. K. (2006). Discounting of past outcomes. Experimental and Clinical Psychopharmacology, 14(3), 311–317.
Zimmerman, D. W. (2007). The privileged present: Defending an ‘A-theory’ of time. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 211–225). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack, Ruth Lee and Patrick Burns for many helpful discussions, and for including me so enthusiastically in their work. I would also like to thank the following people for comments and suggestions: Meghan Sullivan, Alistair Wilson, Natlja Deng, Nick Jones, Tom Dougherty, Scott Sturgeon, Craig Callender, and Tobias Wilsch, as well as audiences at the University of Warwick, and the University of Birmingham. This work was supported by a Research Fellowship at the University of Warwick on the AHRC project ‘Time: Between Metaphysics and Psychology’ (AH/P00217X/1), Principal Investigator Christoph Hoerl and Co-Investigator Teresa McCormack.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Fernandes, A. Does the temporal asymmetry of value support a tensed metaphysics?. Synthese 198, 3999–4016 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02269-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02269-8