Skip to main content
Log in

Scaling up; scaling down: What’s missing?

  • BioBehaviour
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What are we trying to explain when we explain behavior? How is behavior conceptualized as an object of study and how else might it be conceptualized? Longino (Studying human behavior, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 2013) urges pluralism with respect to causes and explanations of behavior. This paper extends Longino’s analysis to the object of those explanations and urges pluralism with respect to behavior itself. The paper proposes that there are three ways in which behavior can be conceptualized, each of which opens to different kinds of research questions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am grateful to Christophe Malaterre and Eric Muzynski for the stimulus to write this paper and to two anonymous reviewers for Synthèse whose comments made this a much better paper than it would otherwise have been.

  2. Evolutionary biology, for example, has seen a resurgence of interest in group selection subsequent to the publication of Sober and Wilson (1998). Ecology has been another arena in biology for debate about units and levels of analysis. See Justus (2014) and Odenbaugh (2007). I will not be discussing these debates here, but focusing on research into proximate factors affecting behavior, especially human behavior.

  3. For a useful review of discussions of methodological individualism in philosophy of social science, see Heath (2015). For a classic defense, see Elster (1982).

  4. For example, Gilbert (1989, 1996) and Epstein (2015).

  5. Longino (2013). The remarks in Sect. 2 will draw heavily on Chapter Nine.

  6. Studying indeed suggests this, but in a muted way.

  7. Population genetics is generally employed in the context of evolutionary biology, to identify changes in gene frequencies in a population. Quantitative behavior genetics, at least as applied to human behavior, is interested in the heritability of a trait in a population.

  8. See Longino (2013, pp. 157–161) for citations to articles using these operationalizations.

  9. Some researchers and reviews distinguish delinquency and aggression, but many do not.

  10. See Klonsky et al. (2002) and Miles and Carey (1997) for disconfirmations of this assumption. They show that different informant categories or different observation settings generate different values for the same individuals, thus casting doubt on the robustness of any data acquired using these methods.

  11. Whalen et al. (1990) proposed the following as dimensions of variation worth study: degree of arousability, frequency of sexual interaction, number of partners, features of partner other than sex/gender identity. Their proposal has not, so far as I can tell, been taken up by fellow researchers.

  12. This analysis draws on ideas first advanced in Longino (2002).

  13. See Longino (2015) for further discussion.

  14. While quantitative behavior genetics measures variance of a trait in a population, the trait is understood as a property of the individual members of the population, and one of the aims of the research is to identify traits for study with other, e.g. molecular, genetic methods that may have a bearing on causal questions. Some researchers have even gone so far as to claim that quantitative behavior genetics can inform about individuals (Burgess and Molenaar 1993).

  15. For examples of aggregative thinking about population level problems, see Brunner et al. (1993) and Moffitt and Mednick (1988).

  16. For examples of non-aggregative reasoning see Fagan et al. (2003) and Anderies et al. (2004).

  17. An exception would be efforts to attribute group differences in average scores on cognitive tests to factors generative of individual difference using twin and adoption studies. These efforts (1) simply assume that a factor making a difference among individuals in one context would have the same effect in another (2) assume that group differences are simply aggregations of individual differences and (3) have been thoroughly critiqued for failing to adequately distinguish one kind of individual level factor from another in the studies performed. See Nisbett et al. (2012) for a recent review.

  18. Eley et al. (1999).

  19. List and Spiekermann (2013).

  20. List and Spiekermann (2013, p. 632).

  21. Ibid, p. 633.

  22. This is shorthand for a more elaborate definition, e.g. this one from De Jaeghere et al. (2010) “Accordingly, we define social interaction as a co-regulated coupling between at least two autonomous agents, where: (i) the co-regulation and the coupling mutually affect each other, constituting an autonomous self-sustaining organization in the domain of relational dynamics and (ii) the autonomy of the agents involved is not destroyed (although its scope can be augmented or reduced).” I imagine interactions among non human entities could be included in a suitably modified version of this definition.

  23. Thanks to Esther Rosario for reminding me of this example. For additional detail see Lloyd (2005).

  24. While still focused on types of individuals, Granic and Lamey (2002) and Granic and Patterson (2006) do begin to take interactions (in their case, mother–son) as an object of investigation.

  25. And, as one reviewer commented, similar issues regarding scaling up and down are likely to arise once we turn the analytic lens on interaction per se.

References

  • Anderies, J. M., Janssen, M. A., & Ostrom, E. (2004). A framework to analyze the robustness of social-ecological systems from an institutional perspective. Ecology and Society, 9(1), 18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunner, H. G. M., Nelen, M., Breakefield, O., Ropers, H. H., & Van Oost, B. A. (1993). Abnormal behavior associated with a point mutation in the structural gene for monoamine oxidase A. Science, 262, 578–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, R. C., & Molenaar, P. (1993). Human behavioral biology. Human Development, 36, 36–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaeghere, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Science, 14(10), 441–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eley, T., Lichtenstein, P., & Stevenson, J. (1999). Sex differences in the etiology of aggressive and non-aggressive antisocial behavior: Results from two twin studies. Child Development, 70(1), 155–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1982). Marxism, functionalism, and game theory: The case for methodologcal individualism. Theory and Society, 11(4), 53–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. (2015). The ant trap. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, J., West, V., & Holland, J. (2003). Reciprocal effects of crime and incarceration in New York City neighborhoods. Fordham Urban Law Journal, 30, 1551–1602.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1996). Living together. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granic, I., & Lamey, Al. (2002). Combining dynamic systems and multivariate analysis to compare the mother–child interactions of externalizing subtypes. Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology, 30, 265–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granic, I., & Patterson, G. (2006). Toward a comprehensive model of antisocial development: A dynamic systems approach. Psychological Review, 113(1), 101–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2015). Methodological individualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/methodological-individualism/. Accessed 18 Aug 2018.

  • Justus, J. (2014). Methodological individualism in ecology. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 770–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klonsky, E. D., Oltmann, T., & Turkheimer, E. (2002). Informant reports of personality disorder: Relations to self-report, and future research directions. Clinical Psychological Science and Practice, 9, 300–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Spiekermann, K. (2013). Methodological individualism and holism in political science: A reconciliation. American Political Science Review, 107(3), 629–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (2005). The case of the female organism: Bias in the science of evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2002). Scientific controversy and the public face of science. In K. Placek, P. Gardenfors, & J. Wolenski (Eds.), Proceedings of the 11th international congress on logic, methodology and philosophy of science. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2013). Studying human behavior. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2015). Individuals or populations. In N. Cartwright & E. Montuschi (Eds.), Philosophy of social science: A new introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miles, D., & Carey, G. (1997). Genetic and environmental architecture of human aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72(1), 207–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moffitt, T., & Mednick, S. A. (1988). Biological contributions to crime causation (NATO Advanced Study Institute, Series D: Behavioral and social Sciences—Number 40). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., Aronson, J., Blair, C., Dickens, W., Flynn, J., Halpern, D. F., et al. (2012). Intelligence: New findings and theoretical developments. American Psychologist, 67(2), 130–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2007). Seeing the forest and the trees: Realism about communities and ecosystems. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 628–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whalen, R., Geary, D., & Johnson, F. (1990). Models of sexuality. In D. P. McWhirter, S. A. E. Sanders, & J. M. E. Reinisch (Eds.), Homosexuality/heterosexuality: Concepts of sexual orientation (pp. 61–70). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Helen E. Longino.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Longino, H.E. Scaling up; scaling down: What’s missing?. Synthese 198, 2849–2863 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02249-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02249-y

Keywords

Navigation